Skip to main content

Full text of "PHYSUCS IN MY GENERATION"

See other formats


105170 



3! 



PHYSICS IN 
MY GENERATION 



PHYSICS IN 
MY GENERATION 

A selection of papers 



MAX BORN 

F.R.S., N.L. 



PERGAMON PRESS 
London &. New YorA 



First published 1956 



Printed in England by 

ADLARD AND SON LIMITED 

London and Dorking 



Published in Great Britain by Pergmon Press, 
4 6? 5 Fit&oy Square, London W.i, and 122 East 
Street, New Tork 22, N.Y. 



CONTENTS 

PAGE 

Preface vii 

Introduction to Einstein's Theory of Relativity (1921) . . i 
Physical Aspects of Quantum Mechanics .... 6 

On the Significance of Collision Processes in the Under- 
standing of Quantum Mechanics . . . .14 

On the Meaning of Physical Theories . . . 1 7 

Some Philosophical Aspects of Modern Physics , . 37 

Cause, Purpose, and Economy in Natural Laws . . . 55 

Einstein's Statistical Theories 80 

Physics and Metaphysics ....... 93 

Physics in the Last Fifty Years . . . . . . 109 

The Conceptual Situation in Physics and the Prospects of 

its Future Development . . . . . .123 

The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics . . . 140 

Physical Reality 151 

Is Classical Mechanics in fact Deterministic ? . . .164 
Astronomical Recollections . . . . . .171 

Statistical Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics . . 177 

Physics and Relativity 189 

Development and Essence of the Atomic Age . , . 207 

A New Year's Message 223 

From the Postscript to The Restless Universe (1951) . * 225 



TO 

SIR EDWARD APPLETON 

G.B.E.,K.C.B.,F.R.S.,N.L. 

Vice-Chancellor and Principal 
of Edinburgh University 



PREFACE 

THE idea of collecting these essays occurred to me when, in the 
leisure of retirement, I scanned some of my own books and found 
that two of the more widely read show a startling change of attitude 
to some of the fundamental concepts of science. These are 
Einstein 9 s Theory of Relativity of 1921 and the American edition of 
The Restless Universe of 1951. I have taken the introduction of the 
former as the first item of this collection, the postscript to the latter 
as its last. These books agree in the relativistic concept of space 
and time, but differ in many other fundamental notions. In 1921 
I believed and I shared this belief with most of my contemporary 
physicists that science produced an objective knowledge of the 
world, which is governed by deterministic laws. The scientific 
method seemed to me superior to other, more subjective ways of 
forming a picture of the world philosophy, poetry, and religion; 
and I even thought the unambiguous language of science to be a 
step towards a better understanding between human beings. 

In 1951 I believed in none of these things. The border between 
object and subject had been blurred, deterministic laws had been 
replaced by statistical ones, and although physicists understood 
one another well enough across all national frontiers they had 
contributed nothing to a better understanding of nations, but had 
helped in inventing and applying the most horrible weapons of 
destruction. 

I now regard my former belief in the superiority of science over 
other forms of human thought and behaviour as a self-deception 
due to youthful enthusiasm over the clarity of scientific thinking 
as compared with the vagueness of metaphysical systems. 

Still, I believe that the rapid change of fundamental concepts 
and the failure to improve the moral standards of human society 
are no demonstration of the uselessness of science in the search for 
truth and for a better life. 

The change of ideas was not arbitrary, but was forced on the 
physicists by their observations. The final criterion of truth is the 
agreement of a theory with experience, and it is only when all 
attempts to describe the facts in the frame of accepted ideas fail 
that new notions are formed, at first cautiously and reluctantly, 
and then, if they are experimentally confirmed, with increasing 



Vlii PREFACE 

confidence. In this way the classical philosophy of science was 
transformed into the modern one, which culminates in NIELS 
BOHR'S Principle of Complementarity. 

To illustrate this process I have selected some of my popular 
writings covering the period of 30 years which lies between the 
publication dates of the books mentioned above, and have framed 
them by the introduction to the first and the postscript to the 
second. Some of the articles are only loosely connected with the 
main theme, such as one on the minimum principles in physics, 
several discussions of EINSTEIN'S work, and a modest attempt at 
autobiography. The remaining articles deal with the philosophical 
background of physics and its revolutionary changes during my 
lifetime. There are many repetitions which could not be avoided 
without spoiling the inner structure of the articles; but I think 
that each treatment of a problem illuminates it from a different 
angle, though all of them are given from my personal point of 
view. The articles are ordered chronologically. 

I hope that the collection may transmit to the reader something 
of the adventurous spirit of a great period of physics. 

I am very much indebted to Dr. D. J. HOOTON for helping me in 
reading the proofs, and to the staff of the publishing firm for their 
willingness to comply with my wishes, and for the excellent printing. 



ACKNOWLEDGMENT 

The author, and the publishers, would like to express 
thanks to those concerned for permission to reproduce 
material first published elsewhere. In every case 
details of first publications are given at the head of 
each article. 



INTRODUCTION TO "EINSTEIN'S THEORY 
OF RELATIVITY" (1921) 

HPHE world is not presented to the reflective mind as a finished 
* product. The mind has to form its picture from innumerable 
sensations, experiences, communications, memories, perceptions. 
Hence there are probably not two thinking people whose picture 
of the world coincides in every respect. 

When an idea in its main lines becomes the common property 
of large numbers of people, the movements of spirit that are called 
religious creeds, philosophic schools, and scientific systems arise; 
they present the aspect of a chaos of opinions, of articles of faith, 
of convictions, that resist all efforts to disentangle them. It seems 
a sheer impossibility to find a thread that will guide us along a 
definite path through these widely ramified doctrines that branch 
off perchance to recombine at other points. 

What place are we to assign to EINSTEIN'S theory of relativity, 
of which this book seeks to give an account? Is it only a special 
part of physics or astronomy, interesting in itself but of no great 
importance for the development of the human spirit? Or is it at 
least a symbol of a particular trend of thought characteristic of 
our times? Or does it itself, indeed, signify a 'world-view* 
(Weltanschauung) ? We shall be able to answer these questions 
with confidence only when we have become acquainted with the 
content of EINSTEIN'S doctrine. But we may be allowed to present 
here a point of view which, even if only roughly, classifies the 
totality of all world-views and ascribes to EINSTEIN'S theory a 
definite position within a uniform view of the world as a whole. 
The world is composed of the ego and the non-ego, the inner 
world and the outer world. The relations of these two poles are 
the object of every religion, of every philosophy. But the part 
that each doctrine assigns to the ego in the world is different. 
The importance of the ego in the world-picture seems to me a 
measure according to which we may order confessions of faith, 
philosophic systems, world-views rooted in art or science, like 
pearls on a string. However enticing it may be to pursue this 
idea through the history of thought, we must not diverge too far 
from our theme, and we shall apply it only to that special realm of 
human thought to which EINSTEIN'S theory belongs to natural 
science. 



2 INTRODUCTION TO EINSTEIN'S THEORY OF RELATIVITY 

Natural science is situated at the end of this series, at the point 
where the ego, the subject, plays only an insignificant part; every 
advance in the mouldings of the concepts of physics, astronomy 
and chemistry denotes a further step towards the goal of excluding 
the ego. This does not, of course, deal with the act of knowing, 
which is bound to the subject, but with the finished picture of 
Nature, the basis of which is the idea that the ordinary world 
exists independently of and uninfluenced by the process of knowing. 

The doors through which Nature imposes her presence on us 
are the senses. Their properties determine the extent of what is 
accessible to sensation or to intuitive perception. The further we 
go back in the history of the sciences, the more we find the natural 
picture of the world determined by the qualities of sense. Older 
physics was subdivided into mechanics, acoustics, optics and theory 
of heat. We see the connexions with the organs of sense, the per- 
ceptions of motion, impressions of sound, light, and heat. Here 
the qualities of the subject are still decisive for the formation of 
concepts. The development of the exact sciences leads along 
a definite path from this state to a goal which, even if far from being 
attained, yet lies clearly exposed before us: it is that of creating a 
picture of nature which, confined within no limits of possible 
perception or intuition, represents a pure structure of concepts, 
conceived for the purpose of depicting the sum of all experiences 
uniformly and without inconsistencies. 

Nowadays mechanical force is an abstraction which has only 
its name in common with the subjective feeling of force. Mech- 
anical mass is no longer an attribute of tangible bodies but is also 
possessed by empty spaces filled only by ether radiation. The 
realm of audible tones has become a small province in the world 
of inaudible vibrations, distinguishable physically from these 
solely by the accidental property of the human ear which makes it 
react only to a definite interval of frequency numbers. Modern 
optics is a special chapter out of the theory of electricity and 
magnetism, and it treats of the electro-magnetic vibrations of all 
wave-lengths, passing from the shortest y-rays of radioactive sub- 
stances (having a wavelength of one hundred millionth of a milli- 
metre) over the X- (Rontgen) rays, the ultraviolet, visible light, the 
infra-red, to the longest wireless (Hertzian) waves (which have a 
wave-length of many kilometres). In the flood of invisible light 
that is accessible to the mental eye of the physicist, the material 
eye is almost blind, so small is the interval of vibrations which it 
converts into sensations. The theory of heat, too, is but a special 
part of mechanics and electrodynamics. Its fundamental concepts 



INTRODUCTION TO EINSTEIN'S THEORY OF RELATIVITY 3 

of absolute temperature, of energy, and of entropy belong to the 
most subtle logical constructions of exact science, and, again, only 
their name still carries a memory of the subjective impression of 
heat or cold. 

Inaudible tones, invisible light, imperceptible heat, these con- 
stitute the world of physics, cold and dead for him who wishes to 
experience living Nature, to grasp its relationships as a harmony, 
to marvel at her greatness in reverential awe. GOETHE abhorred 
this motionless world. His bitter polemic against NEWTON, whom 
he regarded as the personification of a hostile view of Nature, 
proves that it was not merely a question of an isolated struggle 
between two investigators about individual questions of the theory 
of colour. GOETHE is the representative of a world-view which is 
situated somewhere near the opposite end of the scale suggested 
above (constructed according to the relative importance of the 
ego), that is, the end opposite to that occupied by the world-picture 
of the exact sciences. The essence of poetry is inspiration, in- 
tuition, the visionary comprehension of the world of sense in symbolic 
forms. The source of poetry is personal experience, whether it be 
the clearly conscious perception of a sense-stimulus, or the power- 
fully represented idea of a relationship or connexion. What is 
logically formal and rational plays no part in the world-picture of 
such a type of gifted or indeed heaven-blessed spirit. The world 
as the sum of abstractions that are connected only indirectly with 
experience is a province that is foreign to it. Only what is directly 
presented to the ego, only what can be felt or at least represented 
as a possible experience is real to it and has significance for it. 
Thus to later readers, who survey the development of exact methods 
during the century after GOETHE'S time and who measure the 
power and significance of GOETHE'S works on the history of natural 
science by their fruits, these works appear as documents of a 
visionary mind, as the expression of a marvellous sense of one-ness 
with (Einfiihlung) the natural relationships, but his physical 
assertions will seem to such a reader as misunderstandings and 
fruitless rebellions against a greater power, whose victory was 
assured even at that time. 

Now in what does this power consist, what is its aim and device? 

It both takes and renounces. The exact sciences presume to 
aim at making objective statements, but they surrender their 
absolute validity. This formula is to bring out the following 
contrast. 

All direct experiences lead to statements which must be allowed 
a certain degree of absolute validity. If I see a red flower, if I 



4 INTRODUCTION TO EINSTEIN'S THEORY OF RELATIVITY 

experience pleasure or pain, I experience events which it is meaning- 
less to doubt. They are indubitably valid, but only for me. They 
are absolute, but they are subjective. All seekers after human 
knowledge aim at taking us out of the narrow circle of the ego, 
out of the still narrower circle of the ego that is bound to a moment 
of time, and at establishing common ground with other thinking 
creatures. First a link is established with the ego as it is at another 
moment, and then with other human beings or gods. All religions, 
philosophies, and sciences have been evolved for the purpose of 
expanding the ego to the wider community that e we 9 represent. 
But the ways of doing this are different. We are again confronted 
by the chaos of contradictory doctrines and opinions. Yet we no 
longer feel consternation, but order them according to the import- 
ance that is given to the subject in the mode of comprehension 
aimed at. This brings us back to our initial principle, for the 
completed process of comprehension is the world-picture. Here 
again the opposite poles appear. The minds of one group do not 
wish to deny or to sacrifice the absolute, and they therefore remain 
clinging to the ego. They create a world-picture that can be 
produced by no systematic process, but by the unfathomable action 
of religious, artistic, or poetic means of expression in other souls. 
Here faith, pious ardour, love of brotherly communion, but often 
also fanaticism, intolerance, intellectual suppression hold sway. 

The minds of the opposite group sacrifice the absolute. They 
discover often with feelings of terror the fact that inner experi- 
ences cannot be communicated. They no longer fight for what 
cannot be attained, and they resign themselves. But they wish to 
reach agreement at least in the sphere of the attainable. They 
therefore seek to discover what is common in their ego and in that 
of the other egos; and the best that was there found was not the 
experiences of the soul itself, not sensations, ideas, or feelings, but 
abstract concepts of the simplest kind numbers, logical forms; 
in short, the means of expression of the exact sciences. Here we 
are no longer concerned with what is absolute. The height of a 
cathedral does not, in the special sphere of the scientist, inspire 
reverence, but is measured in metres and centimetres. The course 
of life is no longer experienced as the running out of the sands of 
time, but is counted in years and days. Relative measures take 
the place of absolute impressions. And we get a world, narrow, 
one-sided, with sharp edges, bare of all sensual attraction, of all 
colours and tones. But in one respect it is superior to other world- 
pictures: the fact that it establishes a bridge from mind to mind 
cannot be doubted. It is possible to agree as to whether iron has a 



INTRODUCTION TO EINSTEIN'S THEORY OF RELATIVITY 5 

specific gravity greater than wood, whether water freezes more 
readily than mercury, whether Sirius is a planet or a star. There 
may be dissensions, it may sometimes seem as if a new doctrine 
upsets all the old facts, yet he who has not shrunk from the effort 
of penetrating into the interior of this world will feel that the 
regions known with certainty are growing, and this feeling relieves 
the pain which arises from solitude of the spirit, and the bridge to 
kindred spirits becomes built. 

We have endeavoured in this way to express the nature of 
scientific research, and now we can assign EINSTEIN'S theory of 
relativity to its category. 

In the first place, it is a pure product of the striving after the 
liberation of the ego, after the release from sensation and perception. 
We spoke of the inaudible tones, of the invisible light, of physics. 
We find similar conditions in related sciences, in chemistry which 
asserts the existence of certain (radioactive) substances, of which 
no one has ever perceived the smallest trace with any sense directly 
or in astronomy, to which we refer below. These Extensions 
of the world', as we might call them, essentially concern sense- 
qualities. But everything takes place in the space and the time 
which was presented to mechanics by its founder, NEWTON. Now, 
EINSTEIN'S discovery is that this space and this time are still entirely 
embedded in the ego, and that the world-picture of natural science 
becomes more beautiful and grander if these fundamental con- 
cepts are also subjected to relativization. Whereas, before, space 
was closely associated with the subjective, absolute sensation of 
extension, and time with that of the course of life, they are now 
purely conceptual schemes, just as far removed from direct per- 
ception as entities, as the whole region of wave-lengths of present- 
day optics is inaccessible to the sensation of light except for a very 
small interval. But just as in the latter case, the space and time of 
perception allow themselves to be ordered, without giving rise to 
difficulties, into the system of physical concepts. Thus an 
objectivation is attained, which has manifested its power by pre- 
dicting natural phenomena in a truly wonderful way. We shall 
have to speak of this in detail in the sequel. 

Thus the achievement of EINSTEIN'S theory is the relativization 
and objectivation of the concepts of space and time. At the 
present day it is the final picture of the world as presented by 
science. 



PHYSICAL ASPECTS OF QUANTUM 
MECHANICS* 

[First published in Nature, Vol. 119, pp. 354~357> 1927-] 

""pHE purpose of this communication is not to give a report on the 
A present status of quantum mechanics. Such a report has recently 
been published by W. HEISENBERG, the founder of the new theory 
(Die Naturwissenschaften, 45, 989, 1926). Here we shall make an 
attempt to understand the physical significance of the quantum 
theoretical formulae. 

At present we have a surprisingly serviceable and adaptable 
apparatus for the solution of quantum theoretical problems. We 
must insist here that the different formulations, the matrix theory, 
DIRAC'S non-commutative algebra, SGHRODINGER'S partial differen- 
tial equations, are mathematically equivalent to each other, and 
form, as a whole, a single theory. This theory enables us to compute 
the stationary states of atoms and the corresponding radiation, if we 
neglect the reaction of the radiation on the atoms; it would seem 
that in this respect we have nothing more to wish for, since the 
result of every example in which the calculations are carried out 
agrees with experiment. 

This question, however, of the possible states of matter does not 
exhaust the field of physical problems. Perhaps more important still 
is the question of the course of the phenomena that occurs when 
equilibrium is disturbed. Classical physics was entirely concerned 
with this question, as it was almost powerless toward the problem 
of structure. Conversely, the question of the course of phenomena 
practically disappeared from the quantum mechanics, because it 
did not immediately fit into the formal developments of the theory. 
Here we shall consider some attempts to treat this problem on the 
new mechanics. 

In classical dynamics the knowledge of the state of a closed system 
(the position and velocity of all its particles) at any instant deter- 
mines unambiguously the future motion of the system; that is the 
form that the principle of causality takes in physics. Mathematically, 

* Extension of a paper read before Section A (Mathematics and Physics) of the 
British Association at Oxford on August loth, 1926. Translated by Mr. ROBERT 
OPPENHEIMER. The author is very much obliged to Mr. OPPENHEIMER for his 
careful translation. 



PHYSICAL ASPECTS OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 7 

this is expressed by the fact that physical quantities satisfy differen- 
tial equations of a certain type. But besides these causal laws, 
classical physics always made use of certain statistical considerations. 
As a matter of fact, the occurrence of probabilities was justified by 
the fact that the initial state was never exactly known; so long as 
this was the case, statistical methods might be, more or less pro- 
visionally, adopted. 

The elementary theory of probability starts with the assumption 
that one may with reason consider certain cases equally probable, 
and derives from this the probability of complicated combinations 
of these. More generally: starting with an assumed distribution (for 
example, a uniform one, with equally probable cases) a dependent 
distribution is derived. The case in which the derived distribution 
is entirely or partly independent of the assumed initial distribution 
is naturally particularly important. 

The physical procedure corresponds to this: we make an assump- 
tion about the initial distribution, if possible, one about equally 
probable cases, and we then try to show that our initial distribution 
is irrelevant for the final, observable, results. We see both parts of 
this procedure in statistical mechanics: we divide the phase space 
into equally probable cells, guided only by certain general theorems 
(conservation of energy, LIOUVILLE'S theorem) ; at the same time 
we try to translate the resulting space-distribution into a distribu- 
tion in time. But the ergodic hypothesis, which was to effect this 
translation, and states that every system if left to itself covers in 
time its phase space uniformly, is a pure hypothesis and is likely to 
remain one. It thus seems that the justification of the choice of 
equally probable cases by dividing the phase space into cells can 
only be derived a posteriori from its success in explaining the observed 
phenomena. 

We have a similar situation in all cases where considerations of 
probability are used in physics. Let us take as an example an atomic 
collision the collision of an electron with an atom. If the kinetic 
energy of the electron is less than the first excitation potential of 
the atom the collision is elastic: the electron loses no energy. We 
can then ask in what direction the electron is deflected by the 
collision. The classical theory regards each such collision as causally 
determined. If one knew the exact position and velocity of all the 
electrons in the atom and of the colliding electron, one could com- 
pute the deflexion in advance. But unfortunately we again lack this 
information about the details of the system; we have again to be 
satisfied with averages. It is usually forgotten that in order to obtain 
these, we have to make an assumption about equally probable 



8 PHYSICAL ASPECTS OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 

configurations. This we do in the most 'natural 5 way by expressing 
the co-ordinates of the electron in its initial path (relative to the 
nucleus) in terms of angle variables and phases, and by treating 
equal phase intervals as equally probable. But this is only an 
assumption, and can only be justified by its results. 

The peculiarity of this procedure is that the microscopic co- 
ordinates are only introduced to keep the individual phenomena at 
least theoretically determinate. For practical purposes they do not 
exist: the experimentalist only counts the number of particles 
deflected through a given angle, without bothering about the 
details of the path; the essential part of the path, in which the 
reaction of the atom on the electron occurs, is not open to observa- 
tion. But from such numerical data we can draw conclusions about 
the mechanism of the collision. A famous example of this is the work 
of RUTHERFORD on the dispersion of a-particles; here, however, the 
microscopic co-ordinates are not electronic phases, but the distance 
of the nucleus from the original path of the a-particle. From the 
statistics of the dispersion, RUTHERFORD could prove the validity of 
COULOMB'S law for the reaction between the nucleus and the a- 
particle. The microscopic co-ordinate had been eliminated from the 
theoretical formula for the distribution of the particles over different 
angles of deflexion. 

We thus have an example of the evaluation of a field of force by 
counting, by statistical methods, and not by the measurement of an 
acceleration and NEWTON'S second law. 

This method is fundamentally like that which makes us suspect 
that a dice is false if one face keeps turning up much more often than 
every sixth throw; statistical considerations indicate a torque. 
Another example of this is the 'barometer formula'. Of course, we 
can derive this dynamically, if we regard the air as a continuum 
and require equilibrium between hydrodynamical pressure and 
gravity; but actually pressure is only defined statistically as the 
average transport of momentum in the collisions of the molecules, 
and it is therefore not merely permissible but also fundamentally 
more sound to regard the barometer formula as a counting of the 
molecules in a gravitational field, from which the laws of the field 
may be derived. 

These considerations were to lead us to the idea that we could 
replace the Newtonian definition of force by a statistical one. Just 
as in classical mechanics we concluded that there was no external 
force acting if the motion of the particle was rectilinear, so here we 
should do so if an assembly of particles was uniformly distributed 
over a range. (The choice of suitable co-ordinates leads to similar 



PHYSICAL ASPECTS OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 9 

problems on both theories.) The magnitude of a force, classically 
measured by the acceleration of a particle, would here be measured 
by the inhomogeneity of an assembly of particles. 

In the classical theory we are of course faced with the problem 
of reducing the two definitions offeree to one, and that is the object 
of all attempts at a rational foundation of statistical mechanics; we 
have tried to make clear, though, that these have not been altogether 
successful, because in the end the choice of equally probable cases 
cannot be avoided. 

With this preparation we turn our attention to quantum mech- 
anics. It is notable that here, even historically, the concept of a priori 
probability has played a part that could not be thrown back on 
equally probable cases, for example, in the transition-probabilities 
for emission. Of course this might be merely a weakness of the theory. 

It is more important that formal quantum mechanics obviously 
provides no means for the determination of the position of particles 
in space and time. One might object that according to SCHRODINGER 
a particle cannot have any sharply defined position, since it is only a 
group of waves with vague limits; but I should like to leave aside this 
notion of 'wave-packets', which has not been, and probably cannot 
be, carried through. For SCHRODINGER'S waves move not in ordinary 
space but in configuration space, that has as many dimensions as 
the degrees of freedom of the system (3JV for JV particles). The 
quantum theoretical description of the system contains certain 
declarations about the energy, the momenta, the angular momenta of 
the system; but it does not answer, or at least only answers in the 
limiting case of classical mechanics, the question of where a certain 
particle is at a given time. In this respect the quantum theory is in 
agreement with the experimentalists, for whom microscopic co- 
ordinates are also out of reach, and who therefore only count 
instances and indulge in statistics. This suggests that quantum 
mechanics similarly only answers properly-put statistical questions, 
and says nothing about the course of individual phenomena. It 
would then be a singular fusion of mechanics and statistics. 

According to this, we should have to connect with the wave- 
equations such a picture as this: the waves satisfying this equation 
do not represent the motion of particles of matter at all; they only 
determine the possible motions, or rather states, of the matter. 
Matter can always be visualised as consisting of point masses 
(electrons, protons), but in many cases the particles are not to be 
identified as individuals, e.g. when these form an atomic system. 
Such an atomic system has a discrete set of states; but it also has a 
continuous range of them, and these have the remarkable property 



io PHYSICAL ASPECTS OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 

that in them a disturbance is propagated along a path away from 
the atom, and with finite velocity, just as if a particle were being 
thrown out. This fact justifies, even demands, the existence of 
particles, although this cannot, in some cases as we have said, be 
taken too literally. There are electromagnetic forces between these 
particles (we neglect for the moment the finite velocity of propaga- 
tion); they are, so far as we know, given by classical electro- 
dynamics in terms of the positions of the particles (for example, a 
Coulomb attraction). But these forces do not, as they did classically, 
cause accelerations of the particles; they have no direct bearing on 
the motion of the particles. As intermediary there is the wave field: 
the forces determine the vibrations of a certain function i/r that 
depends on the positions of all the particles (a function in configura- 
tion space), and determine them because the coefficients of the 
differential equation for t/r involve the forces themselves. 

A knowledge of i/r enables us to follow the course of a physical 
process in so far as it is quantum-mechanically determinate: not in 
a causal sense but in a statistical one. Every process consists of 
elementary processes, which we are accustomed to call transitions 
or jumps; the jump itself seems to defy all attempts to visualize it, 
and only its result can be ascertained. This result is, that after the 
jump, the system is in a different quantum state. The function i/r 
determines these transitions in the following way: every state of the 
system corresponds to a particular characteristic solution, an 
Eigenfunktiori) of the differential equation; for example, the normal 
state the function i/f 1} the next state ^ 2 , etc. For simplicity we assume 
that the system was originally in the normal state; after the occur- 
rence of an elementary process the solution has been transformed 
into one of the form 



which represents a superposition of a number of eigenfunktions with 
definite amplitudes c lt c z , C B , . . . Then the squares of the amplitudes 
^i 2 j ^a 2 > gi ve the probability that after the jump the system is 
in the i, 2, 3, state. Thus c^ is the probability that in spite of the 
perturbation the system remains in the normal state, 2 2 the prob- 
ability that it has jumped to the second, and so on.* These prob- 
abilities are thus dynamically determined. But what the system 
actually does is not determined, at least not by the laws that are at 

* We may point out that this theory is not equivalent to that of BOHR, KRAMERS, 
and SLATER. In the latter the conservation of energy and momentum are 
purely statistical laws; on the quantum theory their exact validity follows from 
the fundamental equations. 



PHYSICAL ASPECTS of QUANTUM MECHANICS n 

present known. But this is nothing new, for we saw above that the 
classical theory for example, for the collision problem only gave 
probabilities. The classical theory introduces the microscopic co- 
ordinates which determine the individual process, only to eliminate 
them because of ignorance by averaging over their values; whereas 
the new theory gets the same results without introducing them at all. 
Of course, it is not forbidden to believe in the existence of these co- 
ordinates ; but they will only be of physical significance when methods 
have been devised for their experimental observation. 

This is not the place to consider the associated philosophical 
problems; we shall only sketch the point of view which is forced 
upon us by the whole of physical evidence. We free forces of their 
classical duty of determining directly the motion of particles and 
allow them instead to determine the probability of states. Whereas 
before it was our purpose to make these two definitions of force 
equivalent, this problem has now no longer, strictly speaking, any 
sense. The only question is why the classical definition is so useful 
for a large class of phenomena. As always in such cases, the answer 
is : because the classical theory is a limiting case of the new one. 
Actually, it is usually the c adiabatic' case with which we have to 
do: i.e. the limiting case where the external force (or the reaction 
of the parts of the system on each other) acts very slowly. In this 
case, to a very high approximation 



that is, there is no probability for a transition, and the system is in 
the initial state again after the cessation of the perturbation. Such a 
slow perturbation is therefore reversible, as it is classically. One can 
extend this to the case where the final system is really under different 
conditions from the initial one; i.e. where the state has changed 
adiabatically, without transition. That is the limiting case with which 
classical mechanics is concerned. 

It is, of course, still an open question whether these conceptions 
can in all cases be preserved. The problem of collisions was with 
their help given a quantum mechanical formulation ; and the result 
is qualitatively in full agreement with experiment. We have here a 
precise interpretation of just those observations which may be 
regarded as the most immediate proof of the quantized structure of 
energy, namely, the critical potentials, that were first observed by 
FRANCK and HERTZ. This abrupt occurrence of excited states with 
increasing electronic velocity of the colliding electron follows 
directly out of the theory. The theory, moreover, yields general 
formulae for the distribution of electrons over the different angles of 



12 PHYSICAL ASPECTS OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 

deflexion, that differ in a characteristic way from the results that 
we should have expected classically. This was first pointed out by 
W. ELSASSER (Die Naturwissenschqften, Vol. 13, p. 711, 1925) before 
the development of the general theory. He started with DE BROGUE'S 
idea that the motion of particles is accompanied by waves, the 
frequency and wave-length of which is determined by the energy 
and momentum of the particle. ELSASSER computed the wave-length 
for slow electrons, and found it to be of the order of io~ 8 cm., which 
is just the range of atomic diameters. From this he concluded that 
the collision of an electron with an atom should give rise to a 
diffraction of the DE BROGLIE waves, rather like that of light which 
is scattered by small particles. The fluctuation of the intensities in 
different directions would then represent the irregularities in the 
distribution of the deflected electrons. Indications of such an effect 
are given by the experiments of DAVISSON and KUNSMANN (Phys. Rev., 
Vol. 22, p. 243, 1923), on the reflection of electrons from metallic 
surfaces. A complete verification of this radical hypothesis is furnished 
by DYMOND'S experiments on the collisions of electrons in helium 
(Nature, June 13, p. 910, 1925). 

Unfortunately, the present state of quantum mechanics only 
allows a qualitative description of these phenomena; for a complete 
account of them the solution of the problem of the helium atom 
would be necessary. It therefore seems particularly important to 
explain the above-mentioned experiments of RUTHERFORD and his 
co-workers on the dispersion of a-particles; for in this case we have 
to do with a simple and completely known mechanism, the diffrac- 
tion 5 of two charged particles by each other. The classical formula 
which RUTHERFORD derived from a consideration of the hyperbolic 
orbits of the particles, is experimentally verified for a large range; 
but recently BLAGKETT has found departures from this law in the 
encounters between a-particles and light atoms, and has suggested 
that these might also be ascribed to diffraction effects of the DE 
BROGLIE waves. At present only the preliminary question is settled, 
of whether the classical formula can be derived as a limiting case 
of quantum mechanics. G. WENTZEL (Zeit.f. Phys., Vol. 40, p. 590, 
1926) has shown that this is in fact the case. The author of this 
communication has, furthermore, carried through the computation 
for the collision of electrons on the hydrogen atom, and arrived at 
formulae which represent simultaneously the collisions of particles 
of arbitrary energy (from slow electrons to fast a-particles). As yet 
this has only been carried out for the first approximation, and so 
gives no account of the more detailed diffraction effects. This 
calculation thus yields a single expression for the Rutherford 



PHYSICAL ASPECTS oi? QUANTUM MECHANICS 15 

deflexion formula and the cross section of the hydrogen atom for 
electrons in the range studied explicitly by LENARD. The same 
method leads to a calculation of the probability of excitation of the 
H-atom by electronic collision, but the calculations have not yet 
been completed. 

It would be decisive for the theory if it should prove possible to 
carry the approximation further, and to see whether it fUrnishes an 
explanation of the departures from the Rutherford formula. 

Even, however, if these conceptions stand the experimental test, 
it does not mean that they are in any sense final. Even now we can 
say that they depend too much on the usual notion of space and 
time. The formal quantum theory is much more flexible, and 
susceptible of much more general interpretations. It is possible, for 
example, to mix up co-ordinates and momenta by canonical 
transformations, and so to arrive at formally quite different systems, 
with quite different wave functions ijr. But the fundamental idea of 
waves of probability will probably persist in one form or another. 



ON THE SIGNIFICANCE OF COLLISION 
PROCESSES IN THE UNDERSTANDING 
OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 

[First published in Proceedings of the International Conference of Physicists, Como 1927] 

(QUANTUM mechanics, in its original matrix form due to 
^^HEISENBERG, was suited only to the treatment of closed periodic 
systems. It described possible states and transitions; it permitted 
the calculation of the energy levels and of the oscillations of the 
'virtual resonators' associated with the quantum jumps; but it 
could not predict how a system would behave under given external 
conditions. Soon, however, it was seen that, on the basis of matrix 
mechanics, statistical statements at any rate are possible regarding 
the behaviour of a system, provided that the latter is loosely con- 
nected to another system. Its energy is then not constant, and the 
matrix of the energy has non-diagonal elements, but the mean 
value of the matrix is diagonal, and the element denoting the mean 
energy in the ri- state under the action of the perturbation can be 
regarded as the result of quantum jumps between the n^- state 
and all the other states of the unperturbed system. To each jump 
there belongs a transition probability which can be calculated 
from the coupling. Nothing can be said, on the other hand, 
regarding the moment when a quantum jump occurs. The further 
development of quantum mechanics has made its statistical nature 
more and more evident, especially when it became possible to treat 
non-periodic processes. Of the extensions of the matrix calculus 
which have been devised for this purpose, we mention the operator 
calculus, which was introduced by the author together with N. 
WIENER, DIRAG'S ^-number theory and the wave mechanics of 
DE BROGUE and SGHRODINGER. The latter can be formally regarded 
as a special case of the operator theory, although it grew from other 
roots and brings to the fore important physical viewpoints; these 
include the double nature of matter, which, like light, seems in 
many ways to consist of waves and in other ways to consist of 
corpuscles. The most general statement of the operator theory is as 
follows. A physical quantity cannot in general be exactly specified 
by giving the value of a co-ordinate; one can give only a frequency 
law for its distribution over the whole range of variation of the 
co-ordinate. Such a frequency law can in general be determined 
only by an infinite number of numerical data, either by the variation 



COLLISION PROCESSES IN QUANTUM MECHANICS 15 

of a continuous function or by a sequence of discrete numbers; 
these two modes of presentation are, however, not fundamentally 
different, since, for example, a continuous function can be defined 
by specifying the discrete sequence of its Fourier coefficients. 
We therefore represent the distribution law in a wholly abstract 
manner by a point in a space of infinitely many dimensions. A 
Euclidean metric* can be introduced in this space; we then speak 
of a Hilbert space. There are, however, not only rectangular sets 
of discrete axes, but also sets of continuously distributed axes. 
According to the kind of axis on which the point is projected, we 
obtain one or the other of the two representations of the distribution 
law, by number sequences or functions. 

To every physical quantity there corresponds a linear operator, 
i.e. an affine mapping of the Hilbert space on to itself, or, so to 
speak, a homogeneous deformation of that space. Just as in the 
theory of elasticity, there is always a system of principal axes dis- 
tinguished by the fact that the points on the axes are only displaced 
along the axes under the deformation. The magnitude of this 
displacement, i.e. the values of the principal axes of the operator Q 
considered, form the range of values which can be taken by the 
physical quantity; this range may be continuous or discrete. The 
position of the axes with respect to another system of axes is given 
by an orthogonal matrix 0. An operator , whose principal axes 
are known, can be associated with this other system of axes. The 
elements of the matrix <j> are then functions of q' and ),', where 
q' and Q are any two values (principal axes) of the two operatorsf 
q and Q. This quantity $(q', Q} has, according to DIRAG and 
JORDAN, a simple physical significance: | (j)(q'> Q) | 2 represents 
the probability (or probability density) that, for a given Q, the 
variable q' takes a given value (or lies in a given interval A#'). 
is called the probability amplitude. SCHRODINGER'S wave function 
is a special case of this, namely the amplitude belonging to the 
operators q and H(q, [A/27n']#/cty), where H(q,p) is HAMILTON'S 
function; if we denote the principal axes of the latter, as is usual, 
by W, then | <j>(q', W) [ 2 is the probability density that, for a 
given energy, the co-ordinate q' lies in a given interval A#'. 

We will not enter further into the elaboration of this formalism, 
but ask instead what is the empirical evidence for this viewpoint. 
This evidence consists, above all, of the atomic collision processes, 
which almost compel us to interpret the square of the modulus of 

* The expression for the distance, however, is not a quadratic but a Hermitian 
form; all matrices representing physical quantities are not symmetric but 
Hermitian. 

f q' and Q,' niay span spaces of several dimensions. 



jg COLLISION PROCESSES IN OJCJANTUM MECHANICS 

SCHRODINGER'S wave function | <f>(q', W\Y as the number of 
particles. For instance, if we take the case first investigated by 
RUTHERFORD, where a beam of a particles collides with heavy 
atomic nuclei, there corresponds to this a plane wave, which is 
diffracted at the nucleus (by virtue of the Coulomb exchange inter- 
action between the charges) and changed into a spherical wave. 
WENTZEL and OPPENHEIMER have shown that one in fact obtains 
RUTHERFORD'S formula for the number of scattered particles if the 
intensity of the SchrSdinger wave is taken as a measure of the 
probability. The probabilities of excitation and ionization can be 
calculated, even for complex atoms, and one obtains the familiar 
qualitative laws first discovered experimentally by FRANGK and 
HERTZ, which form one of the most secure supports of the whole 
quantum theory. ELSASSER has also investigated the retardation 
of a particles by this method, and has shown that the well-known 
classical theory of BOHR remains valid to some extent. 

DIRAC has recently made a particularly important application 
of this wave-mechanical collision theory by deriving the optical 
dispersion formula with radiation damping. He regards the 
process of scattering of light by atoms as a collision of the light 
quanta with the atoms. Here it is sufficient to associate with the 
atom two steady states: an upper in which the light quantum is 
bound, and a lower in which it is free; in the latter case, the light 
quantum has available a continuum of energy values. This simple 
model suffices for the derivation of the dispersion formula, the 
damping constant (line width) being expressed in terms of the 
coupling between the atom and the light quantum. WIEN'S experi- 
ments on the fading of the light emitted by canal rays can also be 
interpreted in this way, and the same damping constant occurs. 
A more exact investigation of the dependence of the damping 
constant on the properties of the atom and of the spectral line 
considered has yet to be made. 

All these results confirm most impressively the statistical view of 
quantum mechanics. The fundamental determinacy of natural 
processes, always acknowledged in classical physics, must be 
abandoned. The underlying reason for this lies in the dualism of 
waves and corpuscles, which can be formulated as follows. To 
describe natural processes, both continuous and discontinuous 
elements are necessary. The appearance of the latter (corpuscles, 
quantum jumps) is only statistically determined; the probability 
of their appearance, however, is continuously propagated in the 
manner of waves, which obey laws of a form similar to the causal 
laws of classical physics. 



ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL 
THEORIES 

[A lecture given at the public session of 10 November 1928. Nachrichten der 
Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu G6ttingen, Geschaftliche Mitteilungen 1928- 
29-] 

IXTHOEVER regards in a detached way the development of the 
* V exact sciences must be impressed by two contradictory features. 
On the one hand, the whole of natural science exhibits a picture of 
continuous and healthy growth, of unmistakable progress and 
construction, evident as much in its inward deepening as in its 
outward application to the technological mastery of Nature. Yet, 
on the other hand, one observes at not infrequent intervals the 
occurrence of upheavals in the basic concepts of physics, actual 
revolutions in the world of ideas, whereby all our earlier knowledge 
seems to be swept away, and a new epoch of investigation to be 
inaugurated. The abrupt changes in the theories are in marked 
contrast to the continuous flow and growth in the realm of well- 
ascertained results. We may give a few examples of such convulsions 
of theories. Consider the most ancient and most venerable branch 
of physical science, astronomy, and the ideas concerning the stellar 
universe, whose course we can follow through thousands of years. 
At first, the Earth is at rest, a flat disc at the centre of the Universe, 
round which the constellations move in orderly procession. Then, 
almost simultaneously with the realization of the earth's size and 
spherical shape, comes the Gopernican system of the Universe, 
placing the sun in the centre and allotting to the earth only a 
subordinate place among many other attendants of the central star. 
The beginning of the new era in natural science is marked by New- 
ton's theory of gravitation, which holds the solar system together, 
and which remained unchallenged for some two centuries. In our 
time, however, it has been dethroned by EINSTEIN'S relativistic 
theory of gravitation, which completely does away both with the 
heliocentric system of planets and with gravity acting at a distance. 
The position is rather similar in optics, with its change in ideas 
concerning the nature of light, imagined either as a stream of 
small particles, according to NEWTON, or as a train of waves in 
the light-ether, according to HUYGENS. At the beginning of the 
nineteenth century there occurred the sudden change from the 



1 8 ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 

corpuscular theory to the wave theory; the present century, in turn, 
brought with it a fresh transformation, of which I shall speak 
presently. In the study of electricity and magnetism, the middle of 
the last century was a time of revolution, in which the concept 
of action at a distance was compelled to give place to the idea of a 
continuous transmission of force through the ether. The profound 
problem of the structure of matter, which chemistry a mighty 
branch of the tree of physical sciences has made its especial con- 
cern, exhibited even a few decades ago the immemorial antithesis 
of atomistics and the continuum concept. This antithesis today 
seems to be resolved in favour of the former; yet these problems are 
bound up with one of the most fundamental revolutions of ideas, 
which is taking place before our eyes under the name of the quantum 
theory. 

In a smaller scale the rise, acceptance and fall of theories is an 
everyday occurrence; what today is valuable knowledge will 
tomorrow be so much junk, hardly worth a historical backward 
glance. The question thus arises : what then is the value of theories? 
Are they not perhaps a mere by-product of research, a kind of 
metaphysical ornament, draped like a lustrous cloak over the 
'facts' which alone signify, at best a support and aid in our labour, 
stimulants to the imagination in conceiving new experiments ? 

The fact that this question can be proposed at all shows that the 
meaning of physical theories is by no means obvious, and this is 
why I have taken that subject as the theme of my lecture today. 
There are many physicists at the present time, when once again a 
grave crisis regarding the fundamental ideas of physics has just been 
overcome, who are not entirely clear what to think of this latest 
change of theory. 

These theories relativity and the quantum theory which are 
characteristic of the present time, are also the best suited for our 
purposes, since we ourselves feel many of their assertions to be 
strange, paradoxical, or even meaningless. The older theories must 
have had a similar effect on their contemporaries; we, however, 
can conjure up this state of mind only artificially, by historical 
investigation. As I have paid little attention to the study of history, 
I shall content myself with a brief glance backward to earlier periods 
of crisis. 

Any theoretical concept originates from observation and its 
most plausible interpretation. The sight of the fixed, unshakable 
earth on which we are borne, and of the moving heavens, leads 
naturally to the geocentric system of the Universe. The fact that 
light throws sharp shadows can be most simply understood in terms 



ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 1 9 

of the corpuscular hypothesis, which is found already, in poetical 
form, in the works of LUCRETIUS. Of mechanics, which later 
became a model for all physical theories, antiquity knew only 
statics, the science of equilibrium. The reason is, of course, that the 
forces acting upon levers and other machines can be replaced by 
forces exerted by the human (or animal) body, and thus belong to 
the realm of things directly perceptible to the senses. 

What now is the significance of the change, when these primitive 
ideas the geocentric system of the Universe, the corpuscular hypo- 
thesis of light, the statical force in mechanics are replaced by 
others ? The deciding factor is certainly Man's need to believe in a 
real external world, independent of him and permanent, and his 
ability to mistrust his sensations in order to maintain this belief. 
A very distant object seems smaller than when it is near, but Man 
sees always the 'object 5 , imagines it to be always the same size, and 
believes with absolute certainty that he could go and convince 
himself of the fact by touching and feeling the object. The objects 
with which primitive Man deals stones, trees, hills, houses, animals, 
men have the property of meeting this test. Such is the origin 
of geometry, which in its beginnings was entirely the study of the 
mutual positions and size relations of rigid bodies. In this sense 
geometry is the most ancient branch of physics; it first showed 
that objects in the external world. follow strict laws as regards their 
spatial properties. Later, delight in the beauty of these laws had 
the result that the empirical foundations of geometrical science 
were disregarded or even denied, and the study of its logical frame- 
work became an end in itself, as being a part of mathematics. 
The geodesist and the astronomer, however, have always regarded 
the teachings of geometry as statements concerning the real objects 
in the world, and have never doubted that even bodies which, 
because of their remoteness, are not directly accessible to us follow 
the same laws. The application of the rules of geometry to the 
planets showed that they must be very distant and very large, that 
their motions on the night sky are only the projections of their true 
paths in space; and finally the analysis of these paths and the 
refinement of observational technique led of necessity to the COPER- 
NIGAN system. The latter's victory proves that belief in well-tried 
laws is stronger than a direct sense-impression. Of course, the new 
theory must explain the reason for this sense-impression, on which 
the previously accepted doctrine, now recognized to be false, was 
based. In COPERNICUS' case, it sufficed to point out the size of 
the earth in comparison with Man. This astronomical example 
is typical of all subsequent cases. In the stellar universe we have 



20 ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 

for the first time a reality accessible to only one sense, that of 
sight, and then often as an insignificant-seeming impression, far 
removed from the lives and struggles of men, and yet undoubtedly 
just as real as the chair in which I am sitting or the piece of paper 
from which I am reading. This objective reality of which I speak 
is always and everywhere founded on the same principle: obedience 
to the general laws of geometry and physics. Even the chair I 
regard as real only because it exhibits the constant properties 
appertaining to solid bodies of its kind; the geometry and mech- 
anics needed here is at everyone's command from unconscious 
experience. There is no essential difference when we consider 
the reasons why we think the point of light called Mars to be a 
gigantic sphere like the earth; in this case, however, the obser- 
vations must be more exact and geometry and mechanics must 
be consciously applied. The simple and unscientific man's belief 
in reality is fundamentally the same as that of the scientist. Some 
philosophers concede this standpoint, as being practically indis- 
pensable for the scientist; it goes under the name of empirical 
realism and has a precarious position amongst the various kinds 
of idealism. Here, however, we do not wish to discuss the quarrels 
of the different schools of philosophy, but only to state as clearly 
as possible the nature of the reality which forms the subject of 
natural science. It is not the reality of sense-perceptions, of sensa- 
tions, feelings, ideas, or in short the subjective and therefore absolute 
reality of experience. It is the reality of things, of objects, which 
form the substratum underlying perception. We take as a criterion 
of this reality not any one sense-impression or isolated experience, but 
only the accordance with general laws which we detect in phenomena. 

What we have here expounded, using the example of astronomy, 
occurs over and over again in the development of physics. We have 
already ascertained in essentials the meaning of all theories, and 
now wish to show that all the revolutions which have taken place in 
physics are stages on the road to the construction of an objective 
world, which combines the macrocosmos of the stars, the micro- 
cosmos of the atoms and the cosmos of everyday things into a 
consistent whole. 

Let us first consider mechanics. In its period of simplicity it was, 
as we have remarked, unable to progress beyond the study of 
equilibrium. The study of motion or dynamics was the product of 
a more sophisticated age. The laws which GALILEO and NEWTON 
derived from their observations cannot be enunciated without ideas 
which lie far outside the natural limits of thought. Words like 
mass and force had, of course, been used earlier: 'mass 5 meant 



ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 21 

roughly the amount of some material, 'force' the magnitude of an 
exertion. In mechanics, however, these words acquire a new precise 
meaning; they are artificial words, perhaps the first to be coined. 
Their sound is the same as words of ordinary speech, but their 
meaning can be found only from a specially formulated definition. 
I will not discuss this (by no means simple) definition here, but 
merely mention that a concept occurs therein which, in the days 
before science, played no part and can indeed be exactly explained 
only with the aid of mathematical tools, namely the concept of 
acceleration. If mass is defined by means of this concept (as 'resist- 
ance to acceleration'), we already see clearly the foundation of 
mechanics as an artificial product of the mind. Experience of 
terrestrial bodies which could be adduced to support the new 
theory in the period between GALILEO and NEWTON was fairly 
limited. Yet the inner logic of Galilean mechanics was so strong 
that NEWTON was able to take the great step of applying it to the 
motions of the stars. The immense success of this step rests essenti- 
ally on the idea that the force which the heavenly bodies exert on 
one another is fundamentally the same as the gravity which we 
know on earth. This idea, however, caused the abandonment of a 
concept until then generally accepted, namely that forces from a 
body are exerted only on its immediate neighbourhood. Only 
such contact forces were known to statics. Terrestrial gravity, in 
the work of GALILEO, at first appears only as a mathematical aid 
in formulating the laws of falling. NEWTON himself regarded the 
distant action from star to star, which he needed to explain the 
motions of the planets, only as a provisional hypothesis, to be 
later replaced by a contact or near-action. The effect of the 
practical successes of NEWTON'S theory of gravitation on his succes- 
sors was so overwhelming, however, that the distant action of gravi- 
tation was not only taken for granted, but was used as a model for 
the manner of action of other forces, those of electricity and 
magnetism. Fierce battles have been fought in former times over 
this distant action across empty space. Some called it a monstrosity 
opposed to the natural idea of force; others hailed it as a marvellous 
tool for unlocking the secrets of the stellar universe. Who was 
right? We say: the Newtonian force of gravitation is an artificial 
concept, which has little more than its name in common with the 
simple idea, the feeling of force. Its justification rests merely on its 
place in the system of objective natural science. So long as it fulfils 
its duty there, it can remain; but as soon as new observations contra- 
dict it, it must give way for the formation of new ideas, which will 
be required to agree with the distant-action theory within the realm 



22 ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 

of the older observations. This change has occurred only in our 
time, after a long development, which was closely connected with 
the evolution of the sciences of electricity and magnetism. 

As we have already said, the forces of electricity and magnetism 
were, at the time of their first systematic investigation about 150 
years ago, interpreted as distant actions on the model of gravi- 
tation. COULOMB'S law of the attraction of electric charges, BIOT 
and SAVART'S law of the effect of a current on a magnetic pole, 
are imitations of NEWTON'S laws in form and conception. In the 
mathematical construction of the theory, however, a notable thing 
occurred: the so-called potential theory was found to give trans- 
formations of these laws which put them in the form of near actions, 
of forces exerted on one another by adjoining points in space. 
Yet this remarkable equivalence of such heterogeneous concepts 
went almost unnoticed. New discoveries had to be made in order 
to compel a physical decision of the question 'distant or near 
action ?' The discoverer of these new facts was FARADAY, and their 
interpreter was MAXWELL. MAXWELL'S equations are a near- 
action theory of electromagnetic phenomena, and thus signify 
conceptually a return to a mode of thought closer to the natural 
mode. I think, however, that this is quite unimportant. What 
then is the state of affairs ? If we exclude FARADAY'S and MAXWELL'S 
new discoveries, magnetic induction and dielectric displacement 
current, MAXWELL'S equations contain nothing more than the 
already existing potential theory, the mathematical transformation 
of distant-action laws into near-action ones. The change in physical 
theories occurring in the middle of the last cefatury is thus, from this 
viewpoint, not really a revolution, destroying what exists, but a 
conquest of new territory, involving a reorganization of the old 
territory. 

As a result of this conquest, however, a new concept comes to 
the fore, that of the universal ether. For every near-action requires 
a carrier, a substratum between whose particles the forces act, and 
since the electric and magnetic forces can be transmitted even 
through empty space, where no ordinary bodies are present, there 
was nothing for it but to assume an artificial body. This, however, 
was the easier inasmuch as such an ether had already been invented 
in another field, that of optics, and the new theory of electricity 
was in a position to identify this light-ether forthwith with the 
electromagnetic ether. 

We now come to the point where we can glance at the theory 
of light. Here, as has already been remarked, the issue between the 
corpuscular and wave theories had been decided in favour of the 



ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 2$ 

latter at the beginning of the nineteenth century. Far-reaching as 
this decision was, it signified, in the same sense as above, more a 
conquest of new territory with consequent change of government 
than a true revolution. For, so long as the phenomena of 
interference and diffraction remained unknown, the concepts of 
corpuscles and of very short waves were in actual fact equivalent, 
so that the dispute could not be resolved. The fact that the whole 
of the eighteenth century adhered to the corpuscular theory was 
really an accident. Firstly, there was the authority of NEWTON, 
who had preferred the corpuscular theory as being a simpler con- 
cept, in the absence of cogent counter-proofs. Secondly, there 
existed no mathematical proof that, even with short waves, the 
occurrence of apparently sharp shadows can be explained; this 
proof was first furnished by FRESNEL in trying to explain the actual 
diffuseness of shadows, that is, the phenomena of diffraction. As 
soon as these phenomena were discussed, there could no longer be 
any doubt that the wave concept is the correct one. I should like 
to emphasize that this is still true today, although, as we shall see 
presently, the corpuscular theory has had a revival. Just as we 
observe water waves and can follow their propagation, so we can 
detect light waves with our apparatus. It would be entirely irrational 
to employ different words and viewpoints in the two cases. This 
certainty of the existence of light waves leads to the problematical 
features of the most recent optical discoveries, which we shall 
discuss below. 

First of all, however, we must make a few remarks concerning 
the ether problem. Waves require a carrier, and so it was assumed 
that space is filled with the light-ether. The first period of the 
ether theory again showed the simple carrying over of familiar 
viewpoints. Elastic bodies were known to propagate waves, and so it 
was assumed that the ether had the same properties as an ordinary 
elastic substance. It could not, indeed, resemble a gas or a liquid, 
since only longitudinal waves are propagated in the latter, whereas 
experiments with polarized light show that light waves are certainly 
transverse. It was thus necessary to assume a solid elastic ether 
throughout the Universe, through which light waves are propagated. 
It is obvious that this gives rise to difficulties when we try to under- 
stand why the planets and the other heavenly bodies move through 
this substance with no noticeable retardation. Nor was it possible 
to explain satisfactorily the processes of reflection and refraction 
at surfaces, propagation of light in crystals, and such like. It 
was thus a relief when MAXWELL'S theory was experimentally 
confirmed by HERTZ, since it was now possible to equate the 



i>4 ON THE MEANING OP PHYSICAL THEORIES 

electromagnetic ether with the light-ether. The formal difficulties 
disappeared immediately, since the electromagnetic ether is not a 
mechanical body with properties known from ordinary experience, 
but an entity of a special kind, with its own laws like MAXWELL'S 
equations, a typical artificial concept. 

The period in physics following MAXWELL was so packed with 
successes gained by this theory that the belief was often held that 
all the essential laws of the inorganic world had been discovered. 
For it proved possible to fit mechanics also into the 'electromagnetic 
world picture', as it was called; the resistance to acceleration, 
caused by the mass, was ascribed to electromagnetic induction 
effects. Yet the limits of this realm were at hand, visible to the far- 
seeing, and beyond those limits lay new territory which could not 
be mastered by the means at hand. With this we enter the most 
recent period. Its characteristic is that physical criticism takes in 
ideas which no longer belong exclusively to its province, but are 
claimed by philosophy as its own. Here, however, we shall always 
place the physical viewpoints in the foreground. 

As always, the conceptual difficulty came upon the theory of the 
electromagnetic universal ether by a refinement in observational 
technique: I refer to the celebrated Michelson-Morley experiment. 
Before this, the ether could be imagined as a substance at rest 
everywhere in the Universe, having particular properties, and 
LORENTZ was able to show that all the then known electromagnetic 
processes in bodies at rest or in motion could be explained in this 
way. The real difficulty was to explain the fact that no ether wind 
can be detected on the earth, which moves at a considerable speed 
through the ether. LORENTZ was able to show that any optical and 
electromagnetic effects caused by this ether wind must be extremely 
small; they are proportional to the square of the ratio of the earth's 
velocity to that of light, a quantity of the order of io~ 8 . Such small 
quantities were below the limit of observability, until MIGHELSON'S 
experiment was made. This should therefore have revealed the 
blowing aside of light waves by the ether wind. It is well known, 
however, that, like all later repetitions of the experiment, it showed 
no trace of the effect. This was very difficult to explain, and very 
artificial assumptions became necessary, such as the hypothesis put 
forward by FITZ-GERAJLD and LORENTZ that all bodies are shortened 
in the direction of their motion. The riddle was solved by EINSTEIN 
in his 'special' theory of relativity, and the salient point in this was 
a criticism of the idea of time. 

What is time? To the physicist it is not the feeling of elapsion, 
not the symbol of becoming and ceasing to be, but a measurable 



ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 25 

property of processes, like many others. In the naive period of 
science, direct observation or perception of the passage of time 
naturally determines the formation of the concept of time, and the 
one-to-one correspondence between the passage of time and the 
content of experience naturally led to the view that time is the 
same here and everywhere else in the Universe. EINSTEIN was the 
first to question whether this statement has any content that can 
be tested empirically. He showed that the simultaneity of events 
at different places can be ascertained only if an assumption is 
made concerning the velocity of the signals used, and this, in 
conjunction with the negative result of the ether-wind experiment, 
led him to a new definition of simultaneity, which involved a 
relativisation of the concept of time. Two events at different places 
are not in themselves simultaneous; they may be so for one observer, 
but not for another who is in motion relative to the first observer. 
The physical concept of space was also caught up in this change in 
ideas, especially when EINSTEIN, some years later, revealed the 
relation of gravitation to the new conception of space and time. I 
cannot enter into this 'general' theory of relativity within the limits 
of this lecture; I will merely say that, in the theory of gravitation, 
it signifies a transition from distant-action to near-action, and thus 
an approach to intuitive ideas. On the other hand, it demands a 
great step into the abstract: space and time lose all the simple 
properties which before then had made geometry and motion 
theory such convenient tools for physics. The familiar geometry of 
EUCLID and the corresponding time are now reduced to mere 
approximations to reality; but at the same time it becomes un- 
intelligible why humanity has so far obtained such good results 
with this approximation. Even today, one obtains satisfactory 
results with it almost always in practice; in fact, it is an unfortunate 
thing that the deviations capable of testing EINSTEIN'S theory are 
very rare and difficult to observe. Together with the internal 
consistency and logicality of the theory, however, they are enough 
to gain it acceptance from physicists, apart from a few dissenters. 
What is the position regarding the universal ether in the theory 
of relativity? EINSTEIN at first proposed to avoid this concept 
altogether. For the ether might be thought of as a substance having 
at least the most elementary properties in common with ordinary 
substances. These properties include the recognisability and identi- 
fiability of individual particles. In the theory of relativity, however, 
it is meaningless to say, C I have been at this point of the ether 
before.' The ether would be a substance whose parts have neither 
position nor velocity. Nevertheless, EINSTEIN later preferred to 



2 6 ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 

continue to use the word 'ether', as a purely artificial concept, of 
course, having hardly anything in common with the ordinary idea 
of a substance. For it is simply a grammatical necessity, in speaking 
of oscillations and waves in space, to have a subject to govern the 
verb 'to oscillate'. We therefore say, 'The ether oscillates, and does 
so according to the field equations of EINSTEIN'S theory 5 ; and that 
is all we can say about it. 

The theory of relativity also modified importantly the concept of 
mechanical mass, fusing it with that of energy. These are conse- 
quences which are of the greatest significance in physics, in connec- 
tion with investigations of the structure of matter and radiation; 
they have not, however, aroused so much excitement as the criticism 
of the traditional ideas of space and time, since the latter were 
regarded as belonging to the content of philosophy. The fact of 
the matter is as it is agreed by all sensible philosophers that 
philosophy in former times, when the individual sciences had not 
detached themselves, merely took over and retained the concep- 
tions of natural science. Since these conceptions, as always in the 
naive period, corresponded entirely to sense perception many 
schools of thought formed the prejudice that they were an 
immutable property of the mind, experience a priori. This is, of 
course, true in the realm of perception, but not for the objective 
realm of physics, whose properties must always be fitted to the 
progress of experience and its systematic arrangement. 

Much though the theory of relativity has brought in the way of 
innovations, it is yet rather the climax of a development the 
doctrine of the continuous universal ether than the inception of 
a new period. A new period, however, does begin with the present 
century by the introduction of PLANCK'S quantum theory. Its real 
and deepest root is in atomistics, an ancient doctrine going back 
to the Greek philosophers. Before 1900 it had developed quite 
continuously and peacefully, though more and more richly and 
fruitfully. Chemistry first made useful the concept of atoms; 
gradually it conquered physics as well, mainly by explaining the 
properties of gases and solutions, and from there penetrated into 
the theory of electricity. The passage of electricity through electro- 
lytic solutions -led to the hypothesis of atoms of electricity, called 
electrons, and these were so brilliantly established in discharge 
phenomena in gases, and in cathode rays and Becquerel rays, that 
the reality of the electrons soon became as certain as that of the 
material atoms. Now, when the electron had been revealed as a 
kind of sub-atom, investigation was concentrated on the problem 
of decomposing ordinary atoms into their electric component parts. 



ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 27 

The idea was that all atoms are built up of electrically negative 
electrons and of electrically positive components whose nature was 
not yet known. The difficulty is that, according to simple mathe- 
matical theorems, charged bodies can never be at rest in stable 
equilibrium under the known action of electric forces. It was thus 
necessary to assume hypothetical unknown forces, and this is, of 
course, rather unsatisfactory. Then came RUTHERFORD'S great 
discovery. He bombarded atoms with atomic fragments, called 
a-rays, emitted by radioactive bodies; these rays, by virtue of their 
very high velocity, penetrate into the interior of the atoms they 
strike. RUTHERFORD concluded with complete certainty from the 
deflections undergone by the a-rays that they move as if a heavy 
and very small positively charged mass, the 'nucleus', lay at the 
centre of atom, this mass exerting the ordinary electric forces on 
the a-particles. It thus became in the highest degree improbable 
that the atom was held together by unknown non-electric forces. 
But how could the electrons be in equilibrium around the nucleus ? 
The only way out seemed to be to assume that the electrons are 
not at rest, but move in orbits round the nucleus, like the planets 
round the Sun. This, of course, did not help much, since such a 
dynamical system is highly unstable. There is no doubt that 
our planetary system would be reduced to chaos if it were so 
unfortunate as to pass close to another large star; yet the atoms of 
a gas survive a hundred million collisions every second, without 
the slightest change in their properties. 

This astonishing stability of atoms was an utter riddle from the 
standpoint of the theory as it was at the end of the nineteenth 
century, nowadays usually called the 'classical theory' for short. 
An equally difficult puzzle was posed by the gigantic array of facts 
which the spectroscopists had meanwhile assembled. Here one had 
a direct message from the interior of the atom, in the form of light 
oscillations emitted by it, and this message did not sound at all 
like gibberish, but rather like an orderly language except that it 
was unintelligible. For the gases, in particular, a simple structure 
of the spectrum was recognisable: it consists of individual coloured 
lines, each corresponding to a single periodic oscillation, and these 
lines exhibited simple regularities. They can be arranged in series 
in such a way that, from the serial number of the line, its position 
in the spectrum can be calculated, with the greatest accuracy, 
from a simple formula. This was first found by BALMER for hydrogen, 
and later for many other substances by other investigators, in 
particular RUNGE and RYDBERG. The attractive work of photo- 
graphing and measuring spectra appealed to a great number of 



28 ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 

physicists, and so an immense quantity of observational material 
was accumulated over the years, from which many important 
conclusions could be drawn concerning individual problems in 
physics, chemistry and astronomy, but whose real meaning remained 
hidden. It was the same situation as with the extinct Maya peoples, 
of whose script numerous specimens have been found in the ruined 
cities of Yucatan; unfortunately, nobody can read them. 

In physics, the key to the riddle was finally discovered, and that 
by a strangely indirect road. At the turn of the century it was the 
latest fashion to examine the radiation of glowing solid bodies. 
Besides the technological importance of the problem in the manu- 
facture of incandescent lamps and so on, profound theoretical 
results were also hoped for from its solution. For KIRCHHOFF had 
proved, on the basis of unassailable thermodynamic reasoning, that 
radiation which leaves the interior of a glowing furnace through a 
small hole must give a spectrum of an invariable kind, entirely 
independent of the nature of the substances in the furnace and in 
its walls; and this conclusion had been confirmed by experiment. 
From the measurement of 'cavity radiation 5 , results were therefore 
expected concerning quite general properties of the process of 
radiation, and this expectation was not in vain. Nevertheless, it 
now seems remarkable that one of the most profound laws could 
be discovered in this way. For to resume the metaphor of a 
foreign tongue one listened not to the articulate words of indi- 
viduals, but to a crowd shouting all at once, and from this din the 
key word was heard that made all the others intelligible. The 
glowing furnace is such a complex structure, containing innumerable 
oscillating atoms which send out to us their confused assembly of 
waves. The characteristic feature of the spectrum of this assembly 
is, by experiment, that it has a definite colour, according to the 
temperature, red, yellow or white-hot. This means that a certain 
range of oscillations, depending on the temperature, is most strongly 
represented, while the intensity gradually falls to zero on both sides 
of this, towards both rapid and slow oscillations. The classical 
theory, on the other hand, demanded that the intensity should 
continually increase on the side of rapid oscillations. Here there 
was again an insoluble contradiction of the laws accepted at that 
time. 

After countless attempts to ascribe this contradiction to erroneous 
conclusions within the classical theory had proved abortive, PLANCK 
in 1900 ventured to propose a positive assertion amounting to this: 
the energy of the oscillating particles in the furnace alters, not 
continuously by radiation, but discontinuously, in jumps, and the 



ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 29 

ratio of the quantum of energy transferred in each jump to the 
frequency of oscillations in the light emitted or absorbed is a fixed 
and universal constant. This number, today known as PLANCK'S 
constant, could be quite accurately calculated from experiments 
then available on heat radiation, and has since been redetermined 
many tunes by the most various methods, without any considerable 
change in the original value. 

In fact, a new fundamental constant of nature had been dis- 
covered, comparable with the velocity of light or the charge on 
the electron. This no one doubted, but most people found it very 
difficult to accept the hypothesis of energy quanta. EINSTEIN alone 
soon saw that it renders intelligible other peculiarities in the trans- 
formation of mechanical energy into radiation. I must say a few 
words regarding the most important of these phenomena, the so- 
called photoelectric effect. If light of a given frequency falls on a 
metal plate in a high vacuum, it is observed that electrons are 
detached from the plate. The remarkable thing about the process 
is that only the number, and not the velocity, of the electrons 
emitted depends on the intensity of the light. The wave picture is 
of no use in understanding this; for, if we move the metal plate 
away from the light source, the incident wave becomes weaker and 
more and more rarefied, and it is incomprehensible how it can 
always communicate the same energy to an electron. EINSTEIN 
observed that this behaviour can be immediately understood if the 
light does not consist of waves, but is a shower of particles; the 
hail of bullets from a machine-gun thins out with distance, but 
each individual bullet retains its penetrating power. Combining 
this idea with PLANCK'S quantum hypothesis, EINSTEIN predicted 
that the energy of the light particle, and therefore that of the 
ejected electron, must be equal to the frequency multiplied by 
PLANCK'S constant. This result has been entirely confirmed by 
experiments. Thus we have a revival of the old corpuscular theory 
of light in a new form. 

We shall consider below the conflict arising from this. First, 
however, let me say a few words regarding the further development 
of the quantum theory. It is well known that NIELS BOHR conceived 
the idea of using PLANCK'S hypotheses to explain the properties of 
atoms; he supposed that atoms (quite unlike a classical system of 
planets) can exist only in a series of discrete states, and that, in a 
transition from one state to another, light is emitted or absorbed 
whose frequency is to the energy change of the atom in the ratio 
given by PLANCK. By this means, all the contradictions mentioned 
above between experiment and the classical theory are brought 



go ON THE, MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 

back to the same origin, and can be resolved by the assumption of 
discrete energy quanta. The stability of the atom is explained by 
the existence of a 'lowest' quantum state, in which the atom remains 
even when perturbed, provided that the perturbations do not reach 
the amount of the smallest energy jump possible in the atom. The 
existence of this lowest energy threshhold was established experi- 
mentally by FRANCK and HERTZ, who bombarded atoms (of mercury 
vapour) with electrons of measured velocity. At the same time, 
this confirmed BOHR'S hypothesis concerning light emission; for as 
soon as the energy of the bombarding electrons exceeded the first 
energy threshhold, light of a single colour was emitted, its frequency 
being that calculated from the energy by means of PLANCK'S 
relation. The whole of the large amount of observational material 
accumulated by the spectroscopists was thus converted, at one 
stroke, from a collection of numbers and unintelligible rules to a 
most invaluable record regarding the possible states of the atoms 
and the energy differences between them. Further, the previously 
quite enigmatic conditions for the excitation of the various spectra 
became completely intelligible. 

Despite this enormous success of BOHR'S point of view, the road 
from his simple idea of stationary states to a complete and logically 
satisfactory mechanics of the atom was a long and laborious one. 
Here again we have the primitive period, in which the laws of 
ordinary mechanics were applied as far as possible to the electron 
orbits in the atom, and it is remarkable that this was in fact possible 
to some extent, despite the irreconcilable antithesis between the 
continuous nature of the classical quantities and the discontinuous 
processes (jumps) of the quantum theory. Finally, however, the 
necessary modification of mechanics was effected, so as to take 
account of the discontinuities. The new quantum mechanics was 
evolved in different forms, partly from a fundamental idea due to 
HEISENBERG, by one group, here in Gottingen and by DIRAC in 
Cambridge, partly as the so-called wave mechanics of DE BROGLIE 
and SCHRODINGER. These formalisms finally proved to be essentially 
identical; together, they form a logically closed system, the equal 
of classical mechanics in internal completeness and external 
applicability. At first, however, they were only formalisms, and it 
was a matter of discovering their meaning a posteriori. It is, in fact, 
very common in physical investigations to find it easier to derive 
a formal relation from extensive observational material than to 
understand its real significance. The reason for this lies deep in the 
nature of physical experience: the world of physical objects lies 
outside the realm of the senses and of observation, which only 



ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 31 

border on it; and it is difficult to illuminate the interior of an 
extensive region from its boundaries. In the quantum theory, 
there were especial difficulties, of which I should like to discuss the 
most important, namely the revival of the corpuscular theory of 
light. The idea of individually moving light quanta was supported 
by a number of further tests, and in particular by GOMPTON'S 
experiment. This showed that, when such a light quantum collides 
with an electron (realised as the scattering of X-rays by substances, 
such as paraffin, with many loosely-bound electrons) the usual 
collision laws of mechanics hold, as for billiard balls. The primary 
light quantum gives up some energy to the electron with which it 
collides, and so the recoiling light quantum has less energy, and 
by PLANCK'S relation a smaller frequency than the primary one. 
The consequent decrease in frequency of the scattered X-ray has 
been demonstrated experimentally, and so has the existence of 
recoil electrons. 

There is thus no doubt of the correctness of the assertion that 
light consists of particles. But the other assertion that light consists 
of waves is just as correct. In discussing the proofs of the wave 
nature of light, we have seen that, in every phenomenon of inter- 
ference, we can perceive the light waves as clearly and evidently as 
water waves or sound waves. The simultaneous existence of 
corpuscles and waves, however, seems quite irreconcilable. Never- 
theless, the theory must solve the problem of reconciling these two 
ideas, not of course in the realm of observation, but in that of 
objective physical relations, where the only criterion of existence, 
apart from freedom from logical contradiction, is agreement between 
theoretical -predictions and experiment. The solution of this 
problem was attained by a criticism of fundamental concepts, 
very similar to that in the theory of relativity. 

The basis of the entire quantum theory is PLANCK'S relation 
between energy and frequency, which are asserted to be propor- 
tional. In this 'quantum postulate', however, there is an absurdity. 
For the concept of energy clearly refers to a single particle (a light 
quantum or an electron), that is, to something of small extent; the 
concept of frequency, however, belongs to a wave, which must 
necessarily occupy a large region of space, and indeed, strictly 
speaking, the whole of space: if a segment of a purely periodic 
wave-train is removed, it is no longer periodic. The equating of 
the energy of a particle and the frequency of a wave is thus in 
itself quite irrational. It can, however, be made rational, if a 
principle is renounced which was previously always accepted in 
physics, namely, that of determinism. Earlier, it had always been 



32 OK THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 

supposed that the photoelectric process, in which an electron is 
ejected from a metal plate by a light wave, is determined in every 
detail that there is meaning in the question, 'When and where is 
an electron ejected? 3 Or, what is the same thing, "Which light 
quantum, at what point and at what time, takes effect on striking 
the plate? 5 

Suppose that we decide to renounce this question, an act which 
is the easier inasmuch as no experimenter would think of asking it, 
or answering it, in a particular case. It is, in fact, clearly a purely 
artificial question; the experimenter is invariably content to find 
out how many particles appear, and with what energy. 

Let us therefore not ask where exactly a particle is, but be satisfied 
to know that it is in a definite, though fairly large, region of space. 
The contradiction between the wave and corpuscular theories then 
disappears. This is most easily seen if we allot to the wave the 
function of determining the probability that a particle will appear, 
the energy of the particle being related to the frequencies present 
in the wave by means of PLANCK'S relation. If the region of space 
considered is large, and the wave-train consequently almost un- 
perturbed and purely periodic, there corresponds to it a precise 
frequency, and a precisely defined particle energy; but the point 
where the particles appear in this region of space is quite indefinite. 
If it is desired to determine the position of the particles more 
exactly, the region of space in which the process is observed must 
be diminished; by so doing, however, a segment of the wave is 
removed, and its purely periodic character is destroyed; such 
a non-periodic disturbance, nevertheless, can be analysed into a 
greater or lesser number of purely periodic oscillations; to each of 
the various frequencies of this mixture, there then corresponds a 
different energy of the observed particles. Thus an exact deter- 
mination of position destroys the determination of the energy, and 
vice versa. 

This law of restricted measurability discovered by HEISENBERG 
has been confirmed in every case. For every extensive quantity 
(such as determinations of position and time), there is an intensive 
quantity (such as velocity and energy), such that, the more exactly 
the one is determined, the less accurately can the other be deter- 
mined, and it is found that the product of the ranges to within 
which two such associated quantities are known is exactly PLANCK'S 
constant. That is the true significance of this hitherto mysterious 
constant of nature; it is the absolute limit of accuracy of all measure- 
ments. Only its extreme smallness is responsible for the fact that 
its existence was not discovered earlier. 



ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 3 

From this standpoint it is possible to interpret the formalism of 
quantum mechanics, in any individual case, so that the relation 
with the observational concepts of the experimenter is shown, 
without the possibility of any contradiction. 

This, of course, does not happen without the sacrifice of familiar 
ideas. For example, when we speak of a particle, we are accustomed 
to imagine its entire path in a concrete manner. We may continue 
to do so, but we must be careful in drawing conclusions therefrom. 
For, if such an assumed path is to be tested experimentally, the test 
itself will in general alter the path, no matter how carefully it is 
performed. More fundamentally important is the abandonment of 
determinism, the replacement of a rigorously causal description 
by a statistical one. 

Probability and statistics have already played a certain part in 
physics, in the case of phenomena involving large numbers (e.g. in 
the kinetic theory of gases). These methods, however, were usually 
regarded as emergency devices in cases where our knowledge of 
details is insufficient. Provided that the position and velocity of 
all the particles in a closed system were known at some instant, 
the future evolution of the system would be completely determined, 
and could be predicted by mere calculation. This corresponds to 
our experience concerning large bodies. Let us recall the story of 
William Tell. When Tell, before aiming at the apple, sent a 
brief prayer to Heaven, he surely prayed for a steady hand and a 
keen eye, believing that the arrow would then find its way into the 
apple automatically. In precisely the same way, the physicist 
supposed that his electron and a-ray bullets would certainly hit 
any desired atom, provided that he could aim accurately enough, 
and he did not doubt that this was merely a question of practice, 
which could be solved better and better as experimental technique 
progressed. Now, on the contrary, it is asserted that the aiming itself 
can be only of limited accuracy. If Gessler had ordered Tell to 
shoot a hydrogen atom from his son's head by means of an a- 
particle, and given him, instead of a crossbow, the best laboratory 
instruments in the world, then TelTs skill would have been un- 
availing; whether he hit or missed would have been a matter of 
chance. 

The impossibility of exactly measuring all the data of a state 
prevents the predetermination of the further evolution of the system. 
The causality principle, in its usual formulation, thus becomes 
devoid of meaning. For if it is in principle impossible to know all 
the conditions (causes) of a process, it is empty talk to say that every 
event has a cause. Of course, this opinion will be opposed by those 



34 ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 

who see in determinism an essential feature of natural science 
There are others, however, who hold the contrary opinion that 
quantum mechanics asserts nothing new as regards the question 
of determinism; that, even in classical mechanics, determinism is 
only a fiction and of no practical significance*; that, in reality, 
despite mechanics, there holds everywhere the principle that the 
basis of all statistics is small causes, great effects. If, for instance, 
we consider the atoms of a gas as small spheres, the mean free path 
between two collisions is, at normal pressure, many thousands of 
times the diameter of the atom; a very slight deviation in the 
direction of recoil at one collision will therefore convert a direct 
hit at the next collision into a miss, and a marked change of direction 
will be replaced by an undisturbed passage. This is certainly so, 
but it does not yet reach the heart of the matter. Let us return once 
more to Tell What better example could we have of the theorem 
of a small cause and a great effect than shooting at the apple, where 
the accuracy of the aim is a matter of life and death? Yet the story 
is evidently based on the conception of the ideal marksman, who 
can always make the error of his aim smaller than the most diminu- 
tive target supposing, of course, that no unforeseeable influence, 
such as the wind, diverts his missile. In exactly the same way, we 
can imagine an ideal case in classical mechanics; a system com- 
pletely isolated from external influences and an exactly determined 
initial state, and there is no reason to suppose that any approxima- 
tion to this aim is not only difficult but impossible. Quantum 
mechanics, however, asserts that it may be impossible. This 
distinction may seem pointless to the practical scientist; the 
discovery of the existence of an absolute limit of accuracy is, however, 
of great importance in the logical structure of the theory. 

Even if we disregard all philosophical aspects, the contradiction 
between the corpuscular and wave properties of radiation would be 
insoluble in physics without this statistical viewpoint. This is 
where the theory has scored a great success : it predicted on formal 
grounds that even material rays, of emitted atoms or electrons, 
must exhibit a wave character in suitable circumstances, and the 
experimenters have since confirmed this prediction by remarkable 
interference experiments. 

Although the new theory then seems well founded on experiment, 
it may still be asked whether it cannot in future be made again 
deterministic by extension or refinement. To this we may reply 

* R. VON MISES, Probability, Statistics and Truth, Springer, 1928. Compare 
the Mowing argument with the article "Is Classical Mechanics in fact Deter- 
ministic? ", p. 164 of this collection. 



ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 35 

that it can be proved by exact mathematics that the accepted 
formalism of quantum mechanics admits of no such addition. If 
therefore it is desired to retain the hope that determination will 
some day return, the present theory must be regarded as intrinsically 
false; certain statements of this theory would have to be disproved 
by experiment. The determinist must therefore not protest but 
experiment, if he wishes to convert the adherents of the statistical 
theory. 

Of course many people 3 on the contrary, welcome the abandon- 
ment of determinism in physics. I remember that, at the time of 
the appearance of the earliest work on the statistical interpretation 
of quantum mechanics, a gentleman approached me with some 
occultistic pamphlets, thinking I might be suitable for a conversion 
to spiritualism. There are also, however, serious observers of scientific 
evolution, who consider the present turn in physics to be the collapse 
of one conception of the Universe and the beginning of another, 
deeper idea of the nature of 'reality'. Physics itself, they claim, 
admits that there are 'gaps in the sequence of determinateness'. 
What right has it then to put forward its devices as 'realities' ? 

In meeting such arguments it is important to demonstrate clearly 
that the new quantum mechanics is no more and no less revolu- 
tionary than any other newly propounded theory. Once again, it 
is really a conquest of new territory; in the course of this it is 
found, as on previous occasions, that the old principles are no longer 
wholly adequate, and must be in part replaced by new ones. But 
the old ideas still remain as a limiting case, comprising all phenomena 
for which PLANCK'S constant can, on account of its smallness, be 
neglected in comparison with quantities of the same kind. Thus 
events in the world of large bodies obey to a high accuracy the old 
deterministic laws; deviations occur only in the atomic range. If 
quantum mechanics has any peculiarity, it is that it does not decide 
between two modes of presentation (corpuscles and waves) which 
previously were equally possible, but, after the seeming victory of 
one, reinstates the other and combines both in a higher unity. 
The necessary sacrifice is the idea of determinism; but this does 
not mean that rigorous laws of Nature no longer exist. Only the 
fact that determinism is among the ordinary concepts of philosophy 
has caused us to regard the new theory as particularly revolu- 
tionary. 

I hope to have shown that the whole evolution of physical 
theories, up to their latest form, is governed by a consistent striving, 
and the object of this striving will be clear from the individual 
examples given. Let me attempt to express it once more in a 



36 ON THE MEANING OF PHYSICAL THEORIES 

somewhat more general form. The world of Man's experience is 
infinitely rich and manifold, but chaotic and involved with the 
experiencing being. This being strives to arrange his impressions 
and to agree with others concerning them. Language, and art 
with its numerous modes of expression, are such ways of transmission 
from mind to mind, complete in their way where objects of the sense- 
world are concerned, but not well suited to the communication of 
exact ideas concerning the outer world. This marks the beginning 
of the task of science. From the multitude of experiences it selects a 
few simple forms, and constructs from them, by thought, an objective 
world of things. In physics, all 'experience' consists of the activity 
of constructing apparatus and of reading pointer instruments. Yet 
the results thereby obtained suffice to re-create the cosmos by 
thought. At first images are formed which are much influenced 
by observation; gradually, the conceptions become more and 
more abstract; old ideas are rejected and replaced by new ones. 
But, however far the constructed world of things departs from 
observation, nevertheless it is indissolubly linked at its boundaries 
to the perceptions of the senses, and there is no statement of the 
most abstract theory that does not express, ultimately, a relation 
between observations. That is why each new observation shakes 
up the entire structure, so that theories seem to rise and fall. This, 
however, is precisely what charms and attracts the scientist. The 
creation of his mind would be a melancholy thing, did it not die 
and come to life once more. 



SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF 
MODERN PHYSICS 

[Inaugural Lecture as Tait Professor of Natural Philosophy, University of 
Edinburgh. First published in Proc. Roy. Soc. Edinburgh, Vol. LVTI, Part I, pp. 
1-18, 1936-37.] 

HpHE Chair which I have been elected to occupy, in succession 
A to Professor DARWIN, is associated with the name of a great 
scholar of our fathers' generation, PETER GUTHRIE TAIT. This 
name has been familiar to me from the time when I first began to 
study mathematical physics. At that time FELIX KLEIN was the 
leading figure in a group of outstanding mathematicians at Got- 
tingen, amongst them HILBERT and MDSTKOWKSI. I remember how 
KLEIN, ever eager to link physics with mathematics, missed no 
opportunity of pointing out to us students the importance of 
studying carefully the celebrated Treatise on Natural Philosophy of 
THOMSON and TAIT, which became a sort of Bible of mathematical 
science for us. 

To-day theoretical physics has advanced in very different direc- 
tions, and 'Thomson and Tait' is perhaps almost unknown to the 
younger generation. But such is the fate of all scientific achievement; 
for it cannot claim eternal validity like the products of great artists, 
but has served well if it has served its time. For myself this book has 
a special attraction by reason of its title. The subject known every- 
where else in the world by the dull name 'Physics' appears here 
under the noble title of 'Natural Philosophy, 'the same title as is 
given to the two Chairs of Physics in this University. Our science 
acquires by virtue of this name a dignity of its own. Occupied by 
his tedious work of routine measurement and calculation, the 
physicist remembers that all this is done for a higher task: the 
foundation of a philosophy of nature. I have always tried to think 
of my own work as a modest contribution to this task; and in 
entering on the tenure of the Tait Chair of Natural Philosophy at 
this University, though far from my fatherland, I feel intellectually 
at home. 

The justification for considering this special branch of science 
as a philosophical doctrine is not so much its immense object, the 
universe from the atom to the cosmic spheres, as the fact that the 
study of this object in its totality is confronted at every step by 

37 



38 SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF MODERN PHYSICS 

logical and epistemological difficulties; and although the material 
of the physical sciences is only a restricted section of knowledge, 
neglecting the phenomena of life and consciousness, the solution 
of these logical and epistemological problems is an urgent need 
of reason. 

For describing the historical development it is a convenient 
coincidence that the beginning of the new century marks the separa- 
tion of two distinct periods, of the older physics which we usually 
call classical, and modern physics. EINSTEIN'S theory of relativity 
of 1905 can be considered as being at once the culmination of 
classical ideas and the starting-point of the new ones. But during 
the preceding decade research on radiation and atoms, associated 
with the names of RONTGEN, J. J. THOMSON, BECQUEREL, the 
CURIES, RUTHERFORD, and many others, had accumulated a great 
number of new facts which did not fit into the classical ideas at 
all. The new conception of the quantum of action which helped 
to elucidate them was first put forward by PLANCK in 1900. The 
most important consequences of this conception were deduced by 
EINSTEIN, who laid the foundations of the quantum theory of light 
in 1905, the year in which he published his relativity theory, and 
by NIELS BOHR in 1913, when he applied the idea of the quantum 
to the structure of atoms. 

Every scientific period is in interaction with the philosophical 
systems of its time, providing them with facts of observation and 
receiving from them methods of thinking. The philosophy of the 
nineteenth century on which classical physics relied is deeply rooted 
in the ideas of DAVID HUME. From his philosophy there developed 
the two systems which dominated science during the latter part of 
the classical period, critical philosophy and empiricism. 

The difference between these systems concerns the problem of 
the a priori. The idea that a science can be logically reduced to a 
small number of postulates or axioms is due to the great Greek 
mathematicians, who first tried to formulate the axioms of geometry 
and to derive the complete system of theorems from them. Since 
then the question of what are the reasons for accepting just these 
axioms has perpetually occupied the interest of mathematicians and 
philosophers. KANT'S work can be considered as a kind of enormous 
generalization of this question; he attempted to formulate the 
postulates, which he called categories a priori, necessary to build up 
experience in general, and he discussed the roots of their validity. 
The result was the classification of the a priori principles into two 
classes, which he called analytic and synthetic, the former being 
the rules of pure logical thinking, including arithmetic, the latter 



SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF MODERN PHYSICS 39 

containing the laws of space and time, of substance, causality, and 
other general conceptions of this kind. KANT believed that the root 
of the validity of the first kind was c pure reason' itself, whereas the 
second kind came from a special ability of our brain, differing from 
reason, which he called 'pure intuition' (reine Anschauung) . So mathe- 
matics was classified as a science founded on a priori principles, pro- 
perties of our brain and therefore unchangeable; and the same was 
assumed for some of the most general laws of physics, as formulated 
by NEWTON. 

But I doubt whether KANT would have maintained this view if he 
had lived a little longer. The discovery of non-Euclidean geometry 
by LOBATGHEFSKY and BOLYAI shook the a priori standpoint. GAUSS 
has frankly expressed his opinion that the axioms of geometry have 
no superior position as compared with the laws of physics, both 
being formulations of experience, the former stating the general 
rules of the mobility of rigid bodies and giving the conditions for 
measurements in space. Gradually most of the physicists have been 
converted to the empirical standpoint. This standpoint denies the 
existence of a priori principles in the shape of laws of pure reason 
and pure intuition; and it declares that the validity of every state- 
ment of science (including geometry as applied to nature) is based 
on experience. It is necessary to be very careful in this formulation. 
For it is, of course, not meant that every fundamental statement 
as, for instance, the Euclidean axioms of geometry is directly based 
on special observations. Only the totality of a logically coherent 
field of knowledge is the object of empirical examination, and if a 
sufficient set of statements is confirmed by experiment, we can 
consider this as a confirmation of the whole system, including the 
axioms which are the shortest logical expression of the system. 

I do not think that there is any objection to this form of empiric- 
ism. It has the virtue of being free from the petrifying tendency 
which systems of a priori philosophy have. It gives the necessary 
freedom to research, and as a matter of fact modern physics has 
made ample use of this freedom. It has not only doubted the a 
priori validity of Euclidean geometry as the great mathematicians 
did a hundred years ago, but has really replaced it by new forms of 
geometry; it has even made geometry depend on physical forces, 
gravitation, and it has revolutionized in the same way nearly all 
categories a priori, concerning time, substance, and causality. 

This liberation from the idea of the a priori was certainly important 
for the development of science, but it already took place during the 
last century, and does not represent the deciding difference between 
classical and modern physics. This difference lies in the attitude to 



40 SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF MODERN PHYSICS 

the objective world. Classical physics took it for granted that there 
is such an objective world, which not only exists independently of 
any observer, but can also be studied by this observer without 
disturbing it. Of course every measurement is a disturbance of the 
phenomenon observed; but it was assumed that by skilful arrange- 
ment this disturbance can be reduced to a negligible amount. 
It is this assumption which modern physics has shown to be wrong. 
The philosophical problem connected with it arises from the diffi- 
culty in speaking of the state of an objective world if this state 
depends on what the observer does. It leads to a critical examination 
of what we mean by the expression 'objective world.' 

The fact that statements of observations depend on the stand- 
point of the observer is as old as science. The orbit of the earth 
round the sun is an ellipse only for an observer standing just at the 
centre of mass of the two bodies. Relativity gave the first example 
in which the intrusion of the observer into the description of facts 
is not so simple, and leads to a new conception to conserve the 
idea of an objective world. EINSTEIN has acknowledged that his 
studies on this problem were deeply influenced by the ideas of 
ERNST MACH, a Viennese physicist who developed more and more 
into a philosopher. From his writings sprang a new philosophical 
system, logical positivism, which is much in favour to-day. Traces of 
it can be seen in fundamental papers of HEISENBERG on quantum 
theory; but it has also met with strenuous opposition, for instance, 
from PLANCK. In any case, positivism is a living force in science. 
It is also the only modern system of philosophy which by its own 
rules is bound to keep pace with the progress of science. We are 
obliged to define our attitude towards it. 

The characteristic feature of this system is the sharp distinction 
it draws between real and apparent problems, and correspondingly 
between those conceptions which have a real meaning and those 
which have not. Now it is evident and trivial that not every gram- 
matically correct question is reasonable; take, for instance, the 
well-known conundrum: Given the length, beam, and horse-power 
of a steamer, how old is the captain? or the remark of a listener 
to a popular astronomical lecture: C I think I grasp everything, how 
to measure the distances of the stars and so on, but how did they 
find out that the name of this star is Sirius?' Primitive people are 
convinced that knowing the 'correct 5 name of a thing is real know- 
ledge, giving mystical power over it, and there are many instances 
of the survival of such word-fetishism in our modern world. But 
let us now take an example from physics in which the thing is not 
so obvious. Everybody believes he knows what the expression 



SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF MODERN PHYSICS 41 

'simultaneous events' means, and he supposes as a matter of 
course that it means the same for any other individual. This is 
quite in order for neighbours on this little planet. Even when 
science made the step of imagining an individual of similar brain- 
power on another star there seemed to be nothing problematical. 
The problem appeared only when the imagination was driven so 
far as to ask how an observer on the earth and another on, say, 
Mars could compare their observations about simultaneous events. 
It was then necessary to take into account the fact that we are 
compelled to use signals for this comparison. The fastest signal at 
our disposal is a flash of light. In using light, or even only thinking 
about it, we are no longer permitted to rely on our brainpower, our 
intuition. We have to consider facts revealed by experiments. We 
have not only the fact of the finite velocity of light, but another 
most important fact, disclosed by MICHELSON'S celebrated experi- 
ment: that light on this earth travels with the same speed in all 
directions, independently of the motion of the earth round the sun. 
One usually expresses this by saying that these experiments disprove 
the existence of an ether-wind which we would expect from the 
analogy of the wind felt in a moving car. 

An admirable logical analysis of these facts led EINSTEIN to the 
result that the question of simultaneity of two distant events is 
almost as absurd as that regarding the age of the captain. Just as 
this question would become significant by adding some data, say 
about his life insurance, the problem of simultaneity becomes 
reasonable by adding data about the motion of the observer. In 
this way the conception of time loses its absolute character, and 
space becomes involved in this revolution. For it becomes meaning- 
less to speak about 'space at this moment' ; if we assume two ob- 
servers in relative motion just passing one another, then each has 
his own 'space at this moment,' but the events contained in this 
space are different for the two observers. 

What has now become of the idea of a world independent of the 
observer? If one sticks to the meaning of a static assembly of things 
at one moment, this idea of an objective world is lost. But it can be 
saved by considering as the world the assembly of events, each 
having not only a given position in space but also a given time of 
occurrence. MINKOWSKI has shown that it is possible to get a 
description of the connection of all events which is independent of 
the observer, or invariant, as the mathematicians say, by con- 
sidering them as points in a four-dimensional continuum with a 
quasi-Euclidean geometry. But the division of this four-dimensional 
world into space and time depends on the observer. 



42 SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF MODERN PHYSICS 

When I wrote a popular book on relativity in 1920 I was so 
impressed by this wonderful construction that I represented this 
method of objectivation as the central achievement of science. 
I did not then realise that we were soon to be confronted with a 
new empirical situation which would compel us to undertake a 
much deeper critical review of the conception of an objective 
world. 

I have here used the phrase 'new empirical situation, 5 following 
NLELS BOHR, the founder of modern atomic theory, and the deepest 
thinker in physical science. He has coined this expression to indicate 
that the birth of new and strange ideas in physics is not the result 
of free or even frivolous speculation, but of the critical analysis of 
an enormous and complicated body of collected experience. 
Physicists are not revolutionaries but rather conservative, and 
inclined to yield only to strong evidence before sacrificing an 
established idea. In the case of relativity this evidence was strong 
indeed, but consisted to a large extent of negative statements, 
such as that mentioned above regarding the absence of an ether- 
wind. The generalization which was conceived by Einstein in 1915 
combining the geometry of the space-time world with gravitation 
rested, and still rests, on a rather slender empirical basis. 

The second revolution of physics, called quantum theory, is, 
however, built on an enormous accumulation of experience, which 
is still growing from day to day. It is much more difficult to talk 
about these matters, because they have a much more technical 
character. The problem is the constitution of matter and radiation, 
which can be adequately treated only in laboratories with refined 
instruments. The evidence provided there consists of photographic 
plates, and of tables and curves representing measurements. They 
are collected in enormous numbers all over the world, but known 
only to the experts. I cannot suppose that you are acquainted with 
these experiments. In spite of this difficulty, I shall try to outline 
the problem and its solution, called quantum mechanics. 

Let us start with the old problem of the constitution of light. At 
the beginning of the scientific epoch two rival theories were pro- 
posed: the corpuscular theory by NEWTONJ the wave theory by 
HUYGENS. About a hundred years elapsed before experiments were 
found deciding in favour of one of them, the wave theory, by the 
discovery of interference. When two trains of waves are superposed, 
and a crest of one wave coincides with a valley of the other, they 
annihilate one another; this effect creates the well-known patterns 
which you can observe on any pond on which swimming ducks or 
gulls excite water-waves. Exactly the same kind of pattern can be 



SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OP MODERN PHYSICS 43 

observed when two beams of light cross one another, the only 
difference being that you need a magnifying-lens to see them; 
the inference is that a beam of light is a train of waves of short 
wave-length. This conclusion has been supported by innumerable 
experiments. 

But about a hundred years later, during my student days, 
another set of observations began to indicate with equal cogency 
that light consists of corpuscles. This type of evidence can best 
be explained by analogy with two types of instruments of war, 
mines and guns. When a mine explodes you will be killed if you 
are near it, by the energy transferred to you as a wave of compressed 
air. But if you are some hundred yards away you are absolutely 
safe; the explosion-wave has lost its dangerous energy by con- 
tinuously spreading out over a large area. Now imagine that the 
same amount of explosive is used as the propellant in a machine- 
gun which is rapidly fired, turning round in all directions. If you 
are near it you will almost certainly be shot, unless you hastily run 
away. When you have reached a distance of some hundred yards 
you will feel much safer, but certainly not quite safe. The pro- 
bability of being hit has dropped enormously, but if you are hit 
the effect is just as fatal as before. 

Here you have the difference between energy spread out from a 
centre in the form of a continuous wave-motion, and a discon- 
tinuous rain of particles. PLANCK discovered, in 1900, the first 
indication of this discontinuity of light in the laws governing the 
heat radiated from hot bodies. In his celebrated paper of 1905, 
mentioned already, EINSTEIN pointed out that experiments on the 
energetic effect of light, the so-called photoelectric effect, could be 
interpreted in the way indicated as showing unambiguously the 
corpuscular constitution of light. These corpuscles are called quanta 
of light or photons. 

This dual aspect of the luminous phenomenon has been confirmed 
by many observations of various types. The most important step 
was made by BOHR, who showed that the enormous amount of 
observations on spectra collected by the experimentalists could 
be interpreted and understood with the help of the conception of 
light-quanta. For this purpose he had also to apply the idea of 
discontinuous behaviour to the motion of material particles, the 
atoms, which are the source of light. 

I cannot , follow out here the historical development of the 
quantum idea which led step by step to the recognition that we 
have here to do with a much more general conception. Light is 
not the only 'radiation' we know; I may remind you of the cathode 



44 SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF MODERN PHYSICS 

rays which appear when electric currents pass through evacuated 
bulbs, or the rays emitted by radium and other radioactive sub- 
stances. These rays are certainly not light. They are beams of 
fast-moving electrons, i.e. atoms of electricity, or ordinary atoms 
of matter like helium. In the latter case this has been proved 
directly by RUTHERFORD, who caught the beam (a so-called a-ray 
of radium) in an evacuated glass vessel and showed that it was 
finally filled with helium gas. To-day one can actually photograph 
the tracks of these particles of radiating matter in their passage 
through other substances. 

In this case the corpuscular evidence was primary. But in 1924 
DE BROGLIE, from theoretical reasoning, suggested the idea that 
these radiations should show interference and behave like waves 
under proper conditions. This idea was actually confirmed by 
experiments a short time later. Not only electrons, but real atoms 
of ordinary matter like hydrogen or helium have all the properties 
of waves if brought into the form of rays by giving them a rapid 
motion. 

This is a most exciting result, revolutionising all our ideas of 
matter and motion. But when it became known, theoretical physics 
was already prepared to treat it by proper mathematical methods, 
the so-called quantum mechanics, initiated by HEISENBERG, worked 
out in collaboration with JORDAN and myself, and quite inde- 
pendently by DIRAC; and another form of the same theory, the 
wave-mechanics, worked out by SCHRODINGER in close connection 
with DE BROGUE'S suggestion. The mathematical formalism is a 
wonderful invention for describing complicated things. But it does 
not help much towards a real understanding. It took several years 
before this understanding was reached, even to a limited extent, 
But it leads right amidst philosophy, and this is the point about 
which I have to speak. 

The difficulty arises if we consider the fundamental discrepancy 
in describing one and the same process sometimes as a rain of 
particles, and at other times as a wave. One is bound to ask, what 
is it really? You see here the question of reality appears. The 
reason why it appears is that we are talking about particles or 
waves, things considered as well known; but which expression is 
adequate depends on the method of observation. We thus meet a 
situation similar to that in relativity, but much more complicated. 
For here the two representations of the same phenomenon are 
not only different but contradictory. I think everyone feels that a 
wave and a particle are two types of motion which cannot easily 
be reconciled. But if we take into account the simple quantitative 



SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF MODERN PHYSICS 45 

law relating energy and frequency already discovered by PLANCK, 
the case becomes very serious. It is clear that the properties of a 
given ray when appearing as a rain of particles must be connected 
with its properties when appearing as a train of waves. This is 
indeed the case, and the connecting law is extremely simple when 
all the particles of the beam have exactly the same velocity. Experi- 
ment then shows that the corresponding train of waves has the 
simplest form possible, which is called harmonic, and is charac- 
terized by a definite sharp frequency and wave-length. The law 
of PLANCK states that the kinetic energy of the panicles is exactly 
proportional to the frequency of vibration of the wave; the factor 
of proportionality, called PLANCK'S constant, and denoted by the 
letter A, has a definite numerical value which is known from 
experiment with fair accuracy. 

There you have the logical difficulty: a particle with a given 
velocity is, qua particle, a point, existing at any instant without 
extension in space. A train of waves is by definition harmonic only 
if it fills the whole of space and lasts from eternity to eternity! 
[The latter point may not appear so evident; but a mathematical 
analysis made by FOURIER more than a hundred years ago has 
clearly shown that every train of waves finite in space and time 
has to be considered as a superposition of many infinite harmonic 
waves of different frequencies and wave-lengths which are arranged 
in such a way that the outer parts destroy one another by inter- 
ference; and it can be shown that every finite wave can be decom- 
posed into its harmonic components.] BOHR has emphasized this 
pouit by saying that PLANCK'S principle introduces an irrational 
feature into the description of nature. 

Indeed the difficulty cannot be solved unless we are prepared to 
sacrifice one or other of those principles which were assumed as 
fundamental for science. The principle to be abandoned now is 
that of causality as it has been understood ever since it could be 
formulated exactly. I can indicate this point only very shortly. 
The laws of mechanics as developed by GALILEO and NEWTON allow 
us to predict the future motion of a particle if we know its position 
and velocity at a given instant. More generally, the future behaviour 
of a system can be predicted from a knowledge of proper initial 
conditions. The world from the standpoint of mechanics is an 
automaton, without any freedom, determined from the beginning. 
I never liked this extreme determinism, and I am glad that modern 
physics has abandoned it. But other people do not share this view. 

To understand how the quantum idea and causality are con- 
nected, we must explain the second fundamental law relating 



46 SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS Otf MODERN PHYSICS 

particles and waves. This can be readily understood with the help 
of our example of the exploding mine and the machine-gun. If the 
latter fires not only horizontally but equally in all directions, the 
number of bullets, and therefore the probability of being hit, will 
decrease with distance in exactly the same ratio as the surface of 
the concentric spheres, over which the bullets are equally distri- 
buted, increases. But this corresponds exactly to the decrease of 
energy of the expanding wave of the exploding mine. If we now 
consider light spreading out from a small source, we see immediately 
that in the corpuscular aspect the number of photons will decrease 
with the distance in exactly the same way as does the energy of 
the wave in the undulatory aspect. I have generalized this idea for 
electrons and any other kind of particles by the statement that we 
have to do with 'waves of probability' guiding the particles in such 
a way that the intensity of the wave at a point is always propor- 
tional to the probability of finding a particle at that point. This 
suggestion has been confirmed by a great number of direct and 
indirect experiments. It has to be modified if the particles do not 
move independently, but act on one another,- for our purpose, 
however, the simple case is sufficient. 

Now we can analyse the connection between the quantum laws 
and causality. 

Determining the position of a particle means restricting it 
physically to a small part of space. The corresponding probability 
wave must also be restricted to this small part of space, according to 
our second quantum law. But we have seen that by FOURIER'S 
analysis such a wave is a superposition of a great number of simple 
harmonic waves with wave-lengths and frequencies spread over a 
wide region. Using now the first quantum law stating the pro- 
portionality of frequency and energy, we see that this geometrically 
well-defined state must contain a wide range of energies. The 
opposite holds just as well. We have derived qualitatively the 
celebrated uncertainty law of HEISENBERG: exact determination 
of position and velocity exclude one another; if one is determined 
accurately the other becomes indefinite. 

The quantitative law found by HEISENBERG states that for each 
direction in space the product of the uncertainty interval of space 
and that of momentum (equal to mass times velocity) is always the 
same; being given by PLANCK'S quantum constant h. 

Here we have the real meaning of this constant as an absolute 
limit of simultaneous measurement of position and velocity. For 
more complicated systems there are other pairs or groups of physical 
quantities which are not measurable at the same instant. 



SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF MODERN PHYSICS 47 

Now we remember that the knowledge of position and velocity 
at one given time was the supposition of classical mechanics for 
determining the future motion. The quantum laws contradict this 
supposition, and this means the break-down of causality and 
determinism. We may say that these propositions are not just 
wrong, but empty: the premise is never fulfilled. 

The result that the discovery of the quantum laws puts an end 
to the strict determinism which was unavoidable in the classical 
period is of great philosophical importance by itself. After relativity 
has changed the ideas of space and time, another of KANT'S cate- 
gories, causality, has to be modified. The a priori character of these 
categories cannot be maintained. But of course there is not a 
vacuum now where these principles were previously; they are 
replaced by new formulations. In the case of space and time these 
are the laws of the four-dimensional geometry of MINKOWSKI. In 
the case of causality there also exists a more general conception, 
that of probability. Necessity is a special case of probability; it is a 
probability of one hundred per cent. Physics is becoming a funda- 
mentally statistical science. The mathematical theory called quan- 
tum mechanics which expresses these ideas in a precise form is a 
most wonderful structure, not only comparable with, but superior 
to, classical mechanics. The existence of this mathematical theory 
shows that the whole structure is logically coherent. But this proof 
is rather indirect, and convincing only for those who understand 
the mathematical formalism. It is therefore an urgent task to show 
directly for a number of important cases why, in spite of the use of 
two such different pictures as particles and waves, a contradiction 
can never arise. This can be done by discussing special experimental 
arrangements with the help of HEISENBERG'S uncertainty relation. 
In complicated cases this sometimes leads to rather puzzling and 
paradoxical results, which have been carefully worked out by 
HEISENBERG, BOHR and DARWIN, my predecessor in this Chair. 

I shall mention only one case. Looking -through a microscope I 
can see a microbe and follow its motion. Why should it not be 
possible to do the same with atoms or electrons, simply by using 
more powerful microscopes? The answer is that looking through' 
the microscope means sending a beam of light, of photons, through 
it. These collide with the particles to be observed. If these are 
heavy like a microbe or even an atom they will not be essentially 
influenced by the photons, and the deflected photons collected by 
the lenses give an image of the object. But if this is an electron, 
which is very light, it will recoil on colliding with the photon, an 
effect first directly observed by COMPTON. The change of velocity 



48 SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ACf& Of 

of the electron is to some extent indeterminate, and depends ori 
the physical conditions in such a way that HEISENBERG'S uncertainty 
relation is exactly fulfilled in this case also. 

BOHR has introduced the expression 'complementarity' for the 
two aspects of particles and waves. Just as all colours which we see 
can be arranged in pairs of complementary colours giving white 
when mixed, so all physical quantities can be arranged in two 
groups, one belonging to the particle aspect, the other to the wave 
aspect, which never lead to contradictions, but are both necessary 
to represent the full aspect of nature. 

Such a short expression for a complicated and difficult situation 
is very useful, for instance, with respect to the naive question: 
Now, what is a beam of light or a material substance 'really,' a 
set of particles or a wave? Anybody who has understood the 
meaning of complementarity will reject this question as too much 
simplified and missing the point. But this rejection does not solve 
the problem whether the new theory is consistent with the idea of 
an objective world, existing independently of the observer. The 
difficulty is not the two aspects, but the fact that no description of 
any natural phenomenon in the atomistic domain is possible without 
referring to the observer, not only to his velocity as in relativity, 
but to all his activities in performing the observation, setting up 
the instruments, and so on. The observation itself changes the order 
of events. How then can we speak of an objective world ? 

Some theoretical physicists, among them DIRAG, give a short and 
simple answer to this question. They say: the existence of a mathe- 
matically consistent theory is all we want. It represents everything 
that can be said about the empirical world; we can predict with its 
help unobserved phenomena, and that is all we wish. What you 
mean by an objective world we don't know and don't care. 

There is nothing to be objected against this stand-point except 
one thing, that it is restricted to a small circle of experts. I cannot 
share this I' art pour I 9 art standpoint. U think that scientific results 
should be interpreted in terms intelligible to every thinking man. 
To do this is precisely the task of natural philosophy. 

The philosophers to-day concentrate their interest on other 
questions, more important for human life than the troubles arising 
from a refined study of atomistic processes. Only the positivists, 
who claim to have a purely scientific philosophy, have answered 
our question. Their standpoint (JORDAN, 1936) is even more radical 
than that of DIRAG mentioned above. Whereas he declares himself 
content with the formulae and uninterested in the question of an 
objective world, positivism declares the question to be meaningless. 



SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF MODERN PHYSICS 49 

Positivism considers every question as meaningless which cannot 
be decided by experimental test. As I said before, this standpoint 
has proved itself productive by inducing physicists to adopt a critical 
attitude towards traditional assumptions, and has helped in the 
building of relativity and quantum theory. But I cannot agree 
with the application made by the positivists to the general problem 
of reality. If all the notions we use in a science had their origin in 
this science, the positivists would be right. But then science would 
not exist. Although it may be possible to exclude from the internal 
activity of science all reference to other domains of thinking, this 
certainly does not hold for its philosophical interpretation. The 
problem of the objective world belongs to this chapter. 

Positivism assumes that the only primary statements which are 
immediately evident are those describing direct sensual impressions. 
All other statements are indirect, theoretical constructions to 
describe in short terms the connections and relations of the primary 
experiences. Only these have the character of reality. The secondary 
statements do not correspond to anything real, and have nothing 
to do with an existing external world; they are conventions invented 
artificially to arrange and simplify 'economically* the flood of 
sensual impressions. 

This standpoint has no foundation in science itself; nobody can 
prove by scientific methods that it is correct. I would say that its 
origin is metaphysical were I not afraid of hurting the feelings of the 
positivists, who claim to have an entirely unmetaphysical philosophy. 
But I may safely say that this standpoint rests on psychology, only 
it is not a sound psychology. Let us consider it applied to examples 
of everyday life. If I look at this table or this chair I receive innu- 
merable sense-impressions patches of colour and when I move 
my head these impressions change. I can touch the objects and 
get a great variety of new sense-impressions, of varying resistance, 
roughness, warmth, and so on. But if we are honest, it is not these 
un co-ordinated impressions that we observe, but the total object 
'table' or 'chair.' There is a process of unconscious combination, 
and what we really observe is a totality which is not the sum of the 
single impressions, not more or less than this sum, but something 
new. What I mean will perhaps become clearer if I mention an 
acoustical phenomenon. A melody is certainly something else than 
the sum of the tones of which it is composed; it is a new entity. 

Modern psychology is fully aware of this fact. I allude to the 
Gestalt-psychology of v. EHRENFELS, KOHLER, and WERTHEIMER. 
The word Gestalt, which seems to have no adequate English transla- 
tion, means not only shape, but the totality which is really 



50 SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF MODERN PHYSICS 

perceived* I cannot explain it better than by referring again to the 
example of melody. These Gestalten are formed unconsciously; 
when they are considered by the conscious mind they become 
conceptions and are provided with words. The unsophisticated 
mind is convinced that they are not arbitrary products of the mind, 
but impressions of an external world on the mind. I cannot see any 
argument for abandoning this conviction in the scientific sphere. 
Science is nothing else than common sense applied under unac- 
customed conditions. The positivists say that this assumption of 
an external world is a step into metaphysics, and meaningless, 
since we can never know anything about it except by the percep- 
tions of our senses. This is evident. KANT has expressed the same 
point by distinguishing between the empirical thing and the 'thing 
in itself' (Ding an sick] which lies behind it. If the positivists go on 
to say that all our assertions regarding the external world are only 
symbolical, that their meaning is conventional, then I protest. 
For then every single sentence would be symbolical, conventional; 
even if I merely say, 'Here I am sitting on a chair.' The 'chair' is 
no primary sensual impression, but a notion connected with a 
Gestalt, an unconscious integration of the impressions to a new 
unit which is independent of changes in the impressions. For if I 
move my body, my hands, my eyes, the sensual impressions change 
in the most complicated way, but the e chair s remains. The chair is 
invariant with respect to changes of myself, and of other things or 
persons, perceived as Gestalten. This fact, a very obtrusive fact, 
of 'invariance' is what we mean by Saying that there is 'really' a 
chair. It can be submitted to test, not by physical experiment, but 
by the wonderful methods of the unconscious mind, which is able to 
distinguish between a 'real' and a painted chair by merely moving 
the head a little. The question of reality is therefore not meaning- 
less, and its use not merely symbolic or conventional. 

The expression 'invariant' which I have already used in speaking 
of relativity, and which appears here in a more general sense, is 
the link connecting these psychological considerations with exact 
science. It is a mathematical expression first used in analytical 
geometry to handle quantitatively spatial Gestalten, which are 
simple shapes of bodies or configurations of such. I can describe 
any geometrical form by giving a sufficient number of co-ordinates 
of its points; for instance, the perpendicular projections of its points 
on three orthogonal co-ordinate planes. But this is by far too much; 
it describes not only the form but the position relative to the three 
arbitrary planes, which is entirely irrelevant. Therefore one has to 
eliminate all the superfluous, uninteresting parts of the co-ordinate 



SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF MODERN PHYSICS 51 

description by well-known mathematical processes; the result is 
the so-called invariants describing the intrinsic form considered. 

Exactly the same holds if we have to do not only with size and 
shape, but also with colour, heat, and other physical properties. 
The methods of mathematical physics are just the same as those 
of geometry, starting with generalized co-ordinates and eliminating 
the accidental things. These are now not only situation in space, 
but motion, state of temperature or electrification, and so on. 
What remains are invariants describing things. 

This method is the exact equivalent of the formation of Gestalten 
by the unconscious mind of the man unspoiled by science. But 
science transcends the simple man's domain by using refined 
methods of research. Here unknown forms are found, for which the 
unconscious process does not work. We simply do not know what 
we see. We have to think about it, change conditions, speculate, 
measure, calculate. The result is a mathematical theory repre- 
senting the new facts. The invariants of this theory have the right 
to be considered as representations of objects in the real world. 
The only difference between them and the objects of everyday life 
is that the latter are constructed by the unconscious mind, whereas 
the objects of science are constructed by conscious thinking. Living 
in a time in which FREUD'S ideas about the unconscious sphere are 
generally accepted, there seems to be no difficulty in considering 
this difference between common and scientific objects as of second 
order. This is also justified by the fact that the boundary between 
them is not at all sharp, and is continually changing. Conceptions 
which once were purely scientific have become real things. The 
stars were bright points on a spherical shell for the primitive man. 
Science discovered their geometrical relations and orbits. It met 
with furious opposition; GALILEO himself became a martyr to truth. 
To-day these mathematical abstractions are common knowledge of 
school-children, and have become part of the unconscious mind 
of the European. Something similar has happened with the con- 
ceptions of the electromagnetic field. 

This idea that the invariant is the link between common sense 
and science occurred to me as quite natural. I was pleased when 
I found the same idea in the presentation of the Philosophy of Mathe- 
matics by HERMANN WEYL (1926), the celebrated Princeton mathe- 
matician. I think it is also in conformity with BOHR'S (1933) ideas. 
He insists on the point that our difficulties in physics come from the 
fact that we are compelled to use the words and conceptions of 
everyday life even if we are dealing with refined observations. We 
know no other way of describing a motion than either by particles 



52 SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF MODERN PHYSICS 

or waves. We have to apply them also in those cases where observa- 
tion shows that they do not fit completely, or that we really have 
to do with more general phenomena. We develop mathematically 
the invariants describing the new observations, and we learn step 
by step to handle them intuitively. This process is very slow, and 
it proceeds only in proportion as the phenomena become known in 
wider circles. Then the new conceptions sink down into the uncon- 
scious mind, they find adequate names, and are absorbed into the 
general knowledge of mankind. 

In quantum theory we are only at the beginning of this process. 
Therefore I cannot tell you in a few words of ordinary language 
what the reality is which quantum mechanics deals with. I can 
only develop the invariant features of this theory and try to describe 
them in ordinary language, inventing new expressions whenever a 
conception begins to appeal to intuition. This is what teaching of 
physics means. Well-trained youth takes things for granted which 
seemed to us horribly difficult, and later generations will be able 
to talk about atoms and quanta as easily as we are able to talk 
about this table and this chair, and about the stars in heaven. I do 
not, however, wish to belittle the gap between modern and classical 
physics. The idea that it is possible to think about the same pheno- 
mena with the help of two entirely different and mutually exclusive 
pictures without any danger of logical contradiction is certainly new 
in science. BOHR has pointed out that it may help to solve funda- 
mental difficulties in biology and psychology. A living creature, 
plant, or animal is certainly a physico-chemical system. But it is 
also something more than this. There are apparently two aspects 
again. The time of materialism is over; we are convinced that the 
physico-chemical aspect is not in the least sufficient to represent 
the facts of life, to say nothing of the facts of mind. But there is the 
most intimate connection between both spheres; they overlap and 
are inter-woven in the most complicated way. The processes of life 
and mind need other conceptions for their description than the 
physico-chemical processes with which they are coupled. Why do 
these differing languages never contradict each other? BOHR has 
suggested the idea that this is another case of complementarity, 
just as between particles and waves in physics. If you want to study 
a specific biological or psychological process by the methods of 
physics and chemistry, you have to apply all kinds of physical 
apparatus, which disturbs the process. The more you learn about 
the atoms and molecules during the process, the less you are sure 
that the process is that which you want to study. By the time you 
know everything about the atoms, the creature will be dead. This 



SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF MODERN PHYSICS 53 

is briefly BOHR'S suggestion of a new and deeper complementary 
relation between physics and life, body and mind. 

The old desire to describe the whole world in one unique philo- 
sophical language cannot be fulfilled. Many have felt this, but to 
modern physics belongs the merit of having shown the exact logical 
relation of two apparently incompatible trends of thought, by 
uniting them into a higher unit. 

But with this result physics has not come to rest. It is the achieve- 
ment of a bygone period, and new difficulties have appeared since. 
Observations on nuclei, the innermost parts of the atoms, have 
revealed a new world of smallest dimensions, where strange laws 
hold. It has been shown that every kind of atom has a nucleus of 
definite structure, consisting of a very close packing of two kinds of 
particles, called protons and neutrons. The proton is the nucleus 
of the lightest atom, hydrogen, with a positive electric charge. 
The neutron is a particle of nearly the same weight, but uncharged. 
In the atom the nucleus is surrounded by a cloud of electrons, 
which we have mentioned several times. They are particles nearly 
2,000 times lighter than the proton or the neutron; they carry a 
negative charge equal and opposite to that of the proton. But 
recently positive electrons or 'positrons' have also been discovered; 
in fact, their existence was predicted by DIRAC on account of 
theoretical considerations. Hence we have four kinds of particles, 
two 'heavy' ones, proton and neutron, and two e light' ones, the 
negative and positive electron, which can all move with any 
velocity less than that of light. But then there are the photons, 
which can move only with the velocity of light, and very likely 
another kind of particles called 'neutrinos' the motion of which is 
restricted in the same say. 

The question which modern physics raises is: Why just these 
particles ? Of course a question put like this is rather vague, but it 
has a definite meaning. There is, for instance, the ratio of the masses 
of proton and electron, the exact value of which has been found 
to be 1845. Then there is another dimensionless number, 137, con- 
necting the elementary charge, PLANCK'S quantum constant, and 
the velocity of light. To derive these numbers from theory is an 
urgent problem only a theory of this kind does not exist. It would 
have to deal with the relations between the four ultimate particles. 
There has been made the fundamental discovery that a positive 
and a negative electron can unite to nothing, disappear, the energy 
liberated in this process being emitted in the form of photons; and 
vice versa, such a pair can be born out of light. Processes of this 
type, transformations of ultimate particles including birth and 



54 SOME PHILOSOPHICAL ASPECTS OF MODERN PHYSICS 

death, seem to be the key to a deeper understanding of matter. We 
can produce these violent processes in the laboratory only on a very 
small scale, but nature provides us with plenty of material in the 
form of the so-called cosmic rays. In observing them we are witnesses 
of catastrophes in which by the impact of two particles large groups 
of new particles are generated, which have received the suggestive 
name of e showers.' We seem here to be at the limit where the con- 
ception of matter as consisting of distinct particles loses its value, 
and we have the impression that we shall have to abandon some 
other accepted philosophical principle before we shall be able to 
develop a satisfying theory. 

It would be attractive to analyse the indications which our 
present knowledge yields. But my time is over. 

The purpose of my lecture has been to show you that physics, 
besides its importance in practical life, as the fundamental science 
of technical development, has something to say about abstract 
questions of philosophy. There is much scepticism to-day about 
technical progress. It has far outrun its proper use in life. The 
social world has lost its equilibrium through the application of 
scientific results. But Western man, unlike the contemplative 
Oriental, loves a dangerous life, and science is one of his adventures. 

We cannot stop it, but we can try to fill it with a true philosophical 
spirit: the search of truth for its own sake. 

REFERENCES 

BOHR, N. (1933) 'Licht und Leben,' Naturwissenschqften, si, 245. 
JORDAN, P. (1936) A brilliant presentation of the positivistic standpoint 

is given in his book Anschauliche Quantentheorie, J. Springer, Berlin. 
WEYL, H. (1926) 'Philosophic der Mathematik und Naturwissenschaft,' 

Handbuch der Philosophic, Abt. II, A, n. Revised English version: 

Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science, Princetown: University 

Press, 1949. 



CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN 

NATURAL LAWS 
[MINIMUM PRINCIPLES IN PHYSICS] 

[A lecture given at the Royal Institution of Great Britain Weekly Evening 
Meeting, 10 February 1939. First published in Proc. Roy. Inst., Vol. XXX, 
Part iii, 1939.] 

WITHOUT claiming to be a classical scholar I think that the 
earliest reference in literature to the problems which I wish to 
treat to-night is contained in Virgil's Aeneid, Book I, line 368, in the 
words 'taurino quantum possent circumdare tergo'. 

The story, as told at greater length by the later Greek writer 
ZOSIAS, is this: Dido, sister of King Pygmalion of the Phoenician city 
of Tyre, a cruel tyrant who murdered her husband, was compelled 
to fly with a few followers and landed at the site of the citadel of 
Carthago. There she opened negotiations with the inhabitants for 
some land and was offered for her money only as much as she could 
surround with a bull's hide. But the astute woman cut the bull's 
hide into narrow strips, joined them end to end, and with this long 
string encompassed a considerable piece of land, the nucleus of her 
kingdom. To do this she had evidently to solve a mathematical 
question the celebrated problem of Dido: to find a closed curve of 
given circumference having maximum area. 

Well, we do not know how she solved it, by trial, by reasoning or 
by intuition. In any case the correct answer is not difficult to guess, 
it is the circle. But the mathematical proof of this fact has only been 
attained by modern mathematical methods. 

In saying that the first appearance of this kind of problem in 
literature is that quoted above I am not, of course, suggesting that 
problems of minima and maxima had never occurred before in the 
life of mankind. In fact nearly every application of reason to a definite 
practical purpose is more or less an attempt to solve such a problem; 
to get the greatest effect from a given effort, or, putting it the other 
way round, to get a desired effect with the smallest effort. We see 
from this double formulation of the same problem that there is no 
essential distinction between maximum and minimum; we can speak 
shortly of an extremum and extremal problems. The business man uses 
the word 'economy 9 for his endeavour to make the greatest profit out 
of a given investment, or to make a given profit out of the least 

55 



56 CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 

investment. The military commander tries to gain a certain strate- 
gical position with the minimum loss to his side, and maximum loss 
to the enemy a procedure described by the experts by the dubious 
expression 'economy of life'. These examples show how extremal 
problems depend on ideas taken from human desires, passions, 
greeds, hatreds; the ends to be achieved are often utterly unreason- 
able, but once they are accepted as ends they lead to a strictly 
rational question, to be answered by logical reasoning and mathe- 
matics. Our whole life is just this mixture of sense and nonsense, to 
attain by rational methods aims of doubtful character. Consider 
our road system: does it meet the simple requirement of providing 
the shortest connections between inhabited centres ? Certainly not. 




Ax Ax 

FIG. i . Maxima, Minima, Points of Inflexion. 

The roads are the more or less rational resultant of geographical, 
historical and economic conditions,which are often anything but 
rational. 

But here we have to do not with the activities of mankind but 
with the laws of nature. The idea that such laws exist and that they 
can be formulated in a rational way is a comparatively late fruit of 
the human intellect. The nations of antiquity developed only a few 
branches of science, notably geometry and astronomy, both for 
practical purposes. Geometry arose from the surveying of sites and 
from architecture, astronomy from the necessities of the calendar 
and navigation. 

Modern science began with the foundation of mechanics by 
GALILEO and NEWTON. The distinctive quality of these great 
thinkers was their ability to free themselves from the metaphysical 
traditions of their time and to express the results of observations 



CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 57 

and experiments in a new mathematical language regardless of any 
philosophical preconceptions. Although NEWTON was a great theolo- 
gian his dynamical laws are free from the idea that the individual 
motion of a planet might bear witness to a definite and detectable 
purpose. But during his lifetime, at the end of the seventeenth 
century, geometrical and analytical problems of extremals began to 
interest mathematicians, and shortly after NEWTON'S death hi 1727 
the metaphysical idea of purpose or economy in nature was linked 
up with them. 



t" 



2 V 6 7 8 10 12 1V 16 18 20 22 2*\ 
FIG. 2. Diurnal variation of temperature. 

Before I go on to speak of the historical development, let us briefly 
review those geometrical problems exemplified by Dido's land 
purchase from which we started. 

The top of a mountain, the bottom of a valley, are the prototypes 
of maxima and minima; a vertical profile of a mountain range, as 
shown in Fig. i, represents the simplest mathematical figure with 
extremal points and we see that the tangent line is horizontal at 
these points. As the figure shows, there are other points with horizontal 
tangent, but the tangent is a so-called inflexional tangent. The com- 
mon property of these points is that the height is stationary in their 
neighbourhood; it does not change appreciably as it would if the 
point were on a slope. 

You will be acquainted with the method of graphs, representing 
the law of change of any quantity by a curve on co-ordinate paper. 
The diurnal variation of temperature, for instance, is shown by a 



58 CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 

graph like this (Fig. 2); it shows a maximum shortly after noon, 
and a minimum in the small hours of the morning. 

Let us assume that Dido wished to build on her ground a rect- 
angular building with an area as large as possible; this would mean 




FIG. 3. Rectangles of equal circumference and 
different area. 



Sides 
4x4 
3 X5 
2X6 
i x 7 



CiTCUfnference 



2 x (4 + 4 

2 x (3 + 

2 X (2 + 

2 X (I +7 



16 
= 16 
= 16 
= 16 



Area 
16 
15 

12 

7 



a modification, in fact a great simplification of her problem, as 
she would not have to choose the curve of maximum area out of 
all possible closed curves of given length, but merely the rectangle 
of maximum area out of all rectangles of given circumference. Fig. 3 
shows a set of such rectangles which have obviously all a smaller 
area than the square. 




FIG. 4. Rectangles of equal area and different circumference. 



(A 
(B 
(C 
(D 



Sides Area Circumference 

4x4 16 2 x (4 + 4) = 16 

3 X 5*34 16 2 x (3 + 5-34) = 16-7 

2x8 16 2 x (2 + 8) = 20 

i X 16 16 2 x (i + 16) = 34 



This is the simplest form of the genuine isoperimetric problem (from 
the Greek: iso = equal, perimeter = circumference), the general 
case of which is Dido's problem. But mathematicians nowadays use 
this name for all kinds of problems in which an extremum has to 
be determined under a constraining condition (as, for instance, 
maximum area for given circumference). Here one can generally 



CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 59 

interchange the two quantities concerned, whereby a maximum of 
the one becomes a minimum of the other; the square, for instance, 
is clearly also the rectangle of minimum length surrounding a 
given area (Fig. 4) and the corresponding fact holds for the circle 
as compared with all other closed curves. 



FIG. 5. 

Another type of problem is that connected with the idea of the 
shortest line. The simplest case is that of choosing the point Q, on a 
straight line L such that the distance from a given point P outside 
the line may be as short as possible (Fig. 5). It is evident that Q,is 
the foot of the normal from P to the line L. A little more involved 
is the question how to find a point Q/on a straight line L so that 
the sum of its distances PiQ, + QP a from two external points P x , 






Or 

FIG. 6a. 

P 2 is as small as possible. If P 1? P 2 are on different sides of the line L 
the solution is trivial, namely, Q, is the point of intersection of L 
\vith the straight line P^P 2 (Fig. 6a). But if P x and P ? are on the 
same side of L the solution can easily be found by noticing that to 
each point P 2 there belongs an 'image' point P 2 ' on the other side 
of L, and Q,will be the intersection of P X P 2 ' with L (Fig. 6b). This 
idea of an image presents the first example of a physical interpreta- 
tion of such a geometrical problem. For it is evident that if L were 
a plane mirror a beam of light travelling from P x to the mirror and 



6o CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 

reflected to P 2 would just coincide with our solution. This solution 
is exactly the optical law of reflection, and we have expressed this as 
a minimum principle: The beam of light selects just that reflecting 
point Q, which makes the total path P X Q, + QP 2 as short as possible. 
I have here a mechanical model to show this: the point Q,is repre- 
sented by a little peg movable along a bar, and the beam of light 
by a string fixed at one end at P 1? while the other end is in my hand. 
If I pull the string you see that the point Q, adjusts itself so that 
PiQ,, P 2 Q, make equal angles with the line, in agreement with the 
image construction. The light behaves as if each beam had a 
tendency to contract, and the French philosopher FERMAT has 
shown that all the laws of geometrical optics can be reduced to the 
same principle. Light moves like a tired messenger boy who has to 
reach definite destinations and carefully chooses the shortest way 




FIG. 7. 

possible. Are we to consider this interpretation as accidental, or are 
we to see in it a deeper metaphysical significance? Before we can 
form a judgment we must learn more about the facts and consider 
other cases. 

Let us return to geometrical examples. So far we have assumed 
that only straight line connections between different points are 
admitted, or lines composed of straight parts (as in the last example). 
But this restriction is not necessary, and if it is dropped we approach 
the domain of problems to which the real Dido problem belongs, 
namely those where a whole curve has to be determined from the 
condition that some quantity shall be extremal. 

The simplest question of this type is: why is the straight line the 
shortest connection between two given points A and B? (Fig. 7). We 
are here in a much higher branch of mathematics, in the realm of 
infinite possibilities, called the calculus of variations. For we have to 
compare the length of all possible curves passing through A and B, 
that is an infinite number of objects which are not points, but 
figures. It -is one of the great triumphs of the human mind to have 



CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 6 1 

developed methods for performing this apparently superhuman 
task. 

If we travel on our earth we can never go exactly in a straight 
line since the earth's surface is not plane. The best we can do is to 
follow a great circle, which is the curve in which the sphere is inter- 
sected by a plane passing through the centre. Indeed, it can be 
shown that the shortest path between any two points A, B, not being 
the ends of the same diameter ('antipodes'), is the arc of the great 
circle through A and B, or better, the shorter of the two arcs. Ships 
on the ocean should travel on great circles. 

You know that the globe is not an exact sphere but is slightly 
flattened at the poles, bulging at the equator. What, then, about the 
shortest line on such a surface? 

It is just about a hundred years ago that the great mathematician, 
KARL FRIEDRICH GAUSS, in Gottingen, hit on this problem when 
occupied with a geodetic triangulation of his country, the Electorate 
of Hanover. As he was not merely a surveyor but one of the greatest 
thinkers of all times, he attacked the problem from the most general 
standpoint and investigated the shortest lines on arbitrary surfaces. 
But in remembrance of his starting point, he called these lines 
geodesies. I wish to say a few words about these lines and their 
properties, as they are in many ways of fundamental importance 
for physics. 

GAUSS' investigation led him to the discovery of non-euclidean 
geometry. This discovery is generally attributed to the Russian 
LOBATSCHEFSKY and the Hungarian BOLYAI, and this is quite 
correct, as these investigators published independently (about 1830) 
the first systems of non-euclidean geometry. But the discovery (1899) 
of GAUSS' diary many years after his death and the collection and 
publication of his correspondence have given ample evidence that 
a great number of the important mathematical discoveries made by 
others during the first part of the eighteenth century were already 
known to him, among them a complete theory of non-euclidean 
space. He did not publish it because, as he wrote to a friend, he 
was afraid e of the clamour of the Boeotians'. The proof that it is 
possible to construct geometries differing from that of EUCLID 
without meeting contradictions was a fundamental step towards the 
modern development of science. It led to an empirical interpretation 
of geometry as that part of physics which deals with the general 
properties of the form and position of rigid bodies. Through the 
work of RIEMANN and EINSTEIN, geometry and physics gradually 
amalgamated to form a unity. But besides these important develop- 
ments, the study of geodesies teaches us other things which throw 



6'2 CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 

light on the character of different types of physical laws, and on 
our subject of cause, purpose and economy in nature. 

Let us consider a point P on a surface (Fig. 8) and all curves 
through P which have the same direction at P. It is evident that 
there is among them a e straightest curve', i.e. one with the smallest 
curvature. I have a model of a surface with the help of which I can 
.demonstrate to you the straightest curve. There are two small loops 
fixed on the surface, through which I can thread a piece of a piano 
wire. This offers resistance to bending in virtue of its elastic proper- 
ties and, therefore, assumes the straightest shape possible on the 
surface. I now take a piece of string and pull it through the two 
loops. This, of course, assumes the shape of the shortest connection 
between the two points possible on the surface. You see that the 
straightest line and the shortest line coincide accurately. 




FIG. 8. Lines of minimum curvature on a surface. 

Hence the geodesic can be characterized by two somewhat 
different minimum properties : one which can be called a local or 
differential property, namely, to be as little curved as possible at a 
given point for a given direction; and the other, which can be called 
total or integral, namely, to be the shortest path between two points 
on the surface. 

This dualism between 'local' and 'total' laws appears not only 
here in this simple geometrical problem, but has a much wider 
application in physics. It lies at the root of the old controversy 
whether forces act directly at a distance (as assumed in NEWTON'S 
theory of gravitation and the older forms of the electric and magnetic 
theories), or whether they act only from point to point (as in 
FARADAY'S and MAXWELL'S theory of electromagnetism and all 
modern field theories). We can illustrate this by interpreting the 
law of the geodesic itself as a law of physics, in particular of dyna- 
mics. NEWTON'S first law of dynamics, the principle of inertia, states 
that the straight line is the orbit of any small particle moving free 



CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 63 

from external forces; a billiard ball moves in a straight line if the 
table is accurately horizontal so that gravity is inoperative. Imagine 
a frozen lake so large that the curvature of the earth is perceptible 
over its length there is no straight line on it, only straightest lines, 
the great circles of the globe. It is clear that these are the orbits of 
free particles. We can, therefore, extend NEWTON'S first law to the 
motion on smooth surfaces by saying that a body free from external 
forces travels as straight as possible. Here we have a physical law 
of the local character. But, knowing the other minimum property of 
the geodesic, we can also say: a body always moves from one 
position to any other by the shortest possible path which is a law 
of the integral type. 





FIG. 9 (a). Catenary, (b). Chain of four elements carrying a con- 
struction \vhich makes the centre of gravity visible. 

There seems to be no objection to extremal laws of the local type, 
but those of the integral type make our modern mind feel uneasy. 
Although we understand that the particle may choose at a given 
instant to proceed on the straightest path we cannot see how it can 
compare quickly all possible motions to a distant position and choose 
the shortest one this sounds altogether too metaphysical. 

But before we follow out this line of thought we must convince 
ourselves that minimum properties appear in all parts of physics, 
and that they are not only correct but very useful and suggestive 
formulations of physical laws. 

One field in which a minimum principle is of unquestionable 
utility is statics, the doctrine of the equilibrium of all kinds of systems 
under any forces. A body moving under gravity on a smooth 
surface is at rest in stable equilibrium at the lowest point, as this 
pendulum shows. If we have a system composed of different bodies 
forming a mechanism of any kind, the centre of gravity tends to 
descend as far as possible; to find the configuration of stable equi- 
librium one has only to look for the minimum of the height of the 



64 CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 

centre of gravity. This height, multiplied by the force of gravity, is 
called potential energy. 

A chain (Fig. 9 (a) ) hanging from both ends assumes a definite shape, 
which is determined by the condition that the height of the centre 
of gravity is a mininium. If the chain has very many links, we get 
a. curve called the catenary. We have here a genuine variational 
problem of the isoperimetric type, for the catenary has the lowest 
centre among the infinite variety of curves of the same length 
between the given end-points. I have here a chain consisting of only 
four links (Fig. 9(b)). The centre of gravity is made visible by a 




FIG 10. Steel tape carrying a weight (Elastica). 

construction of levers (made from light material so that they do not 
contribute appreciably to the weight). If I disturb the equilibrium 
of the chain in an arbitrary way you observe that the centre of 
gravity is always rising. 

I will now show you an example where gravity competes with 
another force, elasticity (Fig. i o) . I have chosen this special problem, 
not because it was the subject of my doctor's thesis more than 30 years 
ago, but because it can be used to explain the difference between 
the genuine minimum principles of statics and the formal variational 
principles of dynamics, as we shall see later on. A steel tape is 
clamped at one end and carries a weight at the other. This weight 
is pulled downwards by gravity, while the tape tries to resist bending 
in virtue of its elasticity. This elastic force also has a potential 



CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 65 

energy; for a definite amount of work must be done to bend the 
tape into a given curved shape, and it is clear that this energy 
depends in some way on the curvature of the tape which varies 
from point to point. Now there is a definite position of equilibrium, 
which you see here, namely a position in which the total energy, 
that of gravitation plus that of elasticity, is as small as possible; if I 
pull the weight down the gravitational energy decreases, but the 
energy of elastic bending increases more, so that there results a 
restoring force; and if I lift the weight, the gravitational energy 
increases more than the bending energy decreases so that the force 
is again in the direction towards equilibrium. You see that for some 
directions of the clamped end there are two positions of equilibrium, 
one on the left and one on the right. 

This also holds for vertical clamping where the two equilibrium 
forms are symmetrical but only if the tape is long enough. If I 
shorten its length sufficiently, the only possible equilibrium form 
is that in which the tape is straight. There is a definite length for a 
given weight at which this straight form becomes unstable: it is 
determined by the condition that beyond this length the potential 
energy ceases to be a minimum for the straight form and becomes a 
minimum for a curved form. 

The formula for this characteristic length was found by EULER 
and plays an important role in engineering, as it determines the 
strength of vertical bars and columns. But similar instabilities also 
occur for inclined directions of clamping. If I fix the length and 
change the clamping angle, a jump suddenly occurs from one 
position to the one on the opposite side. This instability is again 
determined by the condition of minimum energy. We can summarize 
the facts connected with the limits of stability by drawing a graph, 
not of the elastic lines themselves (which are beautiful curves like 
those shown in Fig. 1 1, called elastica), but by plotting the angle of 
inclination against the distance from the free end. We now obtain 
wave-shaped curves (Fig. 12), all starting horizontally from the line 
representing the end carrying the weight. You see that these curves 
have an envelope and the calculation shows that this envelope is 
just the limit of stability. Through any point on the right of the 
envelope there pass at least two curves; this corresponds to the fact 
that this point represents a clamping angle for which two equilibria 
exist. If we now move vertically upwards in the diagram, we change 
the angle of clamping (without changing the length of the tape) ; 
when we cross the envelope we pass into a region where there is 
only one curve through each point. At the envelope one of the con- 
figurations becomes unstable and jumps across to the other one. In 



66 



CAUSE. PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 



particular EULER'S limit for the stability of the straight form of the 
tape is represented by the sharp point of the envelope; the distance 
of this from the origin is just a quarter of the wave length of the 
neighbour curve, which value gives exactly EULER'S formula. I am 
going to ask you to keep this example in mind as we shall return to 
it later, when we discuss the minimum principles of dynamics. 




t 



N 1 
x > 



FIG. n. Elastica. 

Another example of the statical principle of minimum energy is 
provided by soap bubbles. Soap films have the property of contracting 
as much as possible; the potential energy is proportional to the 
surface-area. A well-known experiment shows this very clearly. I 
project a soap film stretched over a wire in the form of a circle on 
which a fine thread is fixed. If I destroy the film on one side of the 
thread, the film on the other side contracts, the thread is pulled 



CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 



6 7 



tight and assumes- the form of an arc of a circle. I now take a closed 
loop of thread; if I destroy the film in the inner portion the loop 
immediately forms a perfect circle under the stress of the outer film, 
showing that this film is under a uniform tension. 



360* 




FIG. 12. Diagram showing the limits of stability of the elastica. 

It is clear, therefore, that a closed soap bubble filled with air and 
floating freely in space has the shape of a sphere, which is the 
minimum surface for a given volume the spatial analogue of 
Dido's problem. 

There exist other rninirnum surfaces not closed but determined 
by a given boundary. We have only to bend a wire to the shape of 



68 CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 

this boundary and to dip it into a soap solution to get a perfect 
physical model of the minimum surface. These experiments and 
their theory were studied long ago by the blind French physicist, 
PLATEAU, and you will find a wonderful account of them in the 
celebrated little book by G. V. BOYS on Soap Bubbles. I will show you 
some of them. See how expert a mathematician Nature is and how 
quickly she finds the solution ! 

Some of you may consider these experiments merely as pretty 
toys without any serious background. But they are chosen only for 
the sake of illustration. The real importance of the principle of 
minimum energy can scarcely be exaggerated. All engineering 
constructions are based on it, and also all structural problems in 
physics and chemistry. 

As an example, I shall show you here some models of crystal 
lattices. A crystal is a regular arrangement of atoms of definite 
kinds in space. The discovery of LAUE, FRJEDRICH and KNIPPING 
that X-rays are diffracted by these atomic lattices was used by 
Sir WILLIAM BRAGG and his son, Professor W. L. BRAGG, for the 
empirical determination of the atomic arrangements. A great 
number of these are now well known; for instance, here are two 
simple models, each consisting of two kinds of atoms in equal 
numbers per unit of the lattice, but different in structure. One is the 
lattice of a salt, sodium chloride (NaCl), the other of a similar salt, 
caesium chloride (CsCl). The question -arises, why are they dif- 
ferent? The answer can be expected only from a knowledge of the 
forces between the atoms; for it is clear that the structure is deter- 
mined by the condition of minimum potential energy. Conversely, 
a study of this equilibrium condition must teach us something about 
the character of the atomic forces. I have devoted considerable 
energy to research in this field; it could be shown that the forces in 
all these salt crystals are mainly the electrostatic interactions be- 
tween the atoms which are charged, but that the difference of 
stability between the two lattice types has its origin in another 
force, namely the universal cohesion which causes gases to condense 
at low temperatures. This force, called VAN DER WAALS' attraction, 
is larger for bigger atoms; and as the caesium atoms are much 
larger than the sodium atoms the minimum of potential energy is 
attained for different configurations in caesium and sodium salt. 

Considerations of this kind, more or less quantitative, enable us 
to understand a great number of facts about the internal structure of 
solid matter. 

Similar methods can also be applied to the equilibrium of atoms 
in molecules, but I shall not discuss them, for the problem of atomic 



CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 69 

structure is really not one of statics but dynamics, as it involves the 
motion of electrons in the atom. 

Before we proceed to the consideration of minimum principles in 
dynamics where the situation is not as clear and satisfactory as in 
statics, we must first mention another part of physics which in a 
sense occupies an intermediate position between statics and dyna-. 
mics. It is the theory of heat, thermodynamics and statistical mechanics. 
The phenomena considered are of this type. Substances of different 
composition and temperature are brought into contact or mixed 
and the resultant system observed. We have, therefore, to do with 
the transition from one state of equilibrium to another, but we are 
not so much interested in the process itself as in the final result. I 
have here a glass of water and a bottle containing a dye; now I 
pour the red dye into the water and observe the resultant solution. 
If we look for a mechanical process with which to compare these 
processes the nearest is, I think, the elastic steel tape carrying a weight 
which we have already considered. If one end is fixed vertically 
there are two stable equilibria; the system can be made to jump 
over from one to the other by imparting energy to it, but you see 
that it jumps back again. The process is reversible, it leads to a 
definite final equilibrium only if the superfluous energy is taken 
away. But in such a, case as that of the mixture of two liquids a final 
equilibrium is automatically reached and the process is irreversible. 
Not only does it never return spontaneously to the unmixed condi- 
tion, but even the artificial separation of the dye from the water 
cannot be performed by any simple means. 

There is a very important extremum principle, discovered by 
Lord KELVIN, which governs irreversible processes: A certain 
quantity called entropy increases in the process and has a maximum 
for the final equilibrium state. It is not easy to describe this 
miraculous entropy in terms of directly observable quantities, such 
as volume, pressure, temperature, concentration, heat. But its 
meaning is immediately obvious from the standpoint of atomic 
theory. What happens if the red solution spreads in the pure water? 
The molecules of the red dye, at first concentrated in a restricted 
volume, spread out over a greater volume. A state with a higher 
degree of order is replaced by one of less order. To explain this 
expression I have here a model, a flat box, like a little billiard table, 
into which I can put marbles (purchased at Woolworth's for six- 
pence). If I place them carefully in the right-hand half, I have a 
state of partial order; if I shake the box they spread out over the 
whole box and attain a configuration of lower order. If I throw 
20 marbles into the box one after the other so that their position is 



70 CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 

purely accidental it is very improbable that they will all fall in the 
right-hand half. One can easily calculate the probability of a uniform 
distribution over the whole box as compared with one in which the 
majority of the marbles is in the right half; and one finds over- 
whelming odds in favour of the uniform distribution. Now the 
statistical theory of heat interprets the entropy of a system with the 
aid of the probability of the distribution of the atoms, and this helps 
us to understand why entropy always increases and tends to a 



maximum. 



/AAAAA\ 

/A A A A A AY 

YAAAAAAAY 

/AAAAAAAAY 

/AAAAAAAAAY 

/AAAAAAAAAAV 




FIG. 13. Gallon's quincunx. 
(By courtesy of the Institution of Electrical Engineers) 

To show you the working of probability I have here a machine 
(Fig. 13), invented by GALTON and called the quincunx. Shot falls 
from a hole in the centre of the upper end and strikes numerous 
obstacles in the shape of narrow triangles. At each encounter the 
probabilities of falling to the right and to the left are equal. It is 
clear that a ball has very little chance of always being deflected in 
the same direction; therefore the cells collecting the balls at the 
bottom will be comparatively empty at the end, and fuller in the 
middle. The middle cell corresponds to those balls which have been 
deflected an equal number of times to the right and to the left, that 
is to the uniform distribution of deflections. You see that there is 
a clear maximum. This demonstrates the uniform distribution of 
the marbles or of the red dye molecules. 



CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 71 

The thermodynamical principle of maximum entropy is, there- 
fore, really a statistical law and has very little to do with dynamics 
at all. If a system is initially in a state of partial order, that is in a 
state which is not the most probable one (which would correspond 
to the middle cell of the quincunx) it is very probable that after a 
while it will have approached the state of maximum probability 
or maximum entropy. Very probable, indeed but not absolutely 
certain. And the modern technique of micro-observations has 
revealed cases where deviations from the most probable state are 
detectable. The extremal principle of statistical mechanics is, there- 
fore, somewhat different in character from the similar laws of pure 
mechanics. But I cannot go more deeply into the difficult questions 
of the role of chance and probability in science. 



Straight line 




FIG. 14. Brachistochrone. 

Let us now come back to the minimum principles of dynamics. 

The first problem of this kind first both in historical order and 
hi order of simplicity was formulated at the end of the seventeenth 
century by JOHANN BERNOULLI of Basle, one of a great family which 
produced many famous scholars and especially many mathemati- 
cians. It is the problem of the curve of quickest descent or brachisto- 
chrone (Greek: brachys = short, chronos = time) : given two points 
at different levels, not in the same vertical, to determine a connecting 
curve in such a way that the time taken by a body to slide without 
friction under the action of gravity from the higher point to the 
lower is a minimum compared, of course, with all possible curves 
through the two points. I have here a model illustrating this prob- 
lem, but instead of an infinite number of curves I have only three, 
a straight line, an arc of a circle, and an intermediate curve (Fig. 
14). Instead of the bodies sliding without friction I use steel ball- 
bearings rolling on two rails. This has the advantage not only of 
diminishing friction, but also of retarding the whole motion, which 



72 CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 

would be too fast without this precaution. As the distance between 
the rails is a fraction of the diameter of the sphere, it advances for 
each full rotation only a fraction of the distance it would advance 
if rolling on a smooth surface. The effect of this trick is only to 
increase the inertia without changing the gravitational force; the 
laws of motion are unchanged, only the time scale is reduced. 

Now, before I start a race between three balls I ask you to bet 
if you like which ball will win, and I am prepared to act as book- 
maker. It is, of course, not any actual virtue of the ball to be the 
fastest but of the shape of the curve on which it is rolling. 

You see that it is not the straight line which carries the winner, 
nor the steep descent of the circular arc, but just the intermediate 
curve. If you were to try with any other curves you would always 
find the same result; for this curve has been constructed according 
to the theoretical calculation. It is a so-called cycloid, a curve which 
you can observe hundreds of times every day on the road. It is the 
curve traced out by a point on the circumference of a wheel rolling 
along a straight line; I have here a circular disc with a piece of 
chalk attached to it and if I roll it along the blackboard you see the 
chalk drawing this line. 

The determination of this brachistochronic property of the cycloid 
was a very satisfactory piece of mathematics; it is a genuine mini- 
mum problem and its solution was a great achievement. It attracted 
much attention and there is no philosopher of this period who did 
not test his analytical powers by solving similar extremal problems. 
Another member of the Bernoulli family, DANIEL BERNOULLI, 
developed during the beginning of the eighteenth century the 
minimum principle of statics which we have already treated, and 
applied it to the catenary and the elastic line. Encouraged by these 
successes DANIEL BERNOULLI raised the question whether it was 
possible to characterize the orbit, and even the motion in the orbit, 
of a body subject to given forces for example, a planet by a 
minimum property of the real motion as compared with all other 
imagined or virtual motions. He put this question to the foremost 
mathematician of his time, LEONARD EULER, who was very much 
interested in. it and spent several years in investigating it. In the 
autumn of 1743 he found a solution which he explained with the 
help of various examples in an appendix to a book on isoperimetric 
problems published in 1744. It is the basis of the principle of least 
action which has played so prominent a part in physics right up to 
the present time. But the history of this principle is an amazing 
tangle of controversies, quarrels over priority and other unpleasant 
things. MAUPERTUIS, in the same year, 1744, presented a paper to 



CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 7$ 

the Paris Academy in which he substituted for FERMAT'S optical 
principle of the shortest light path, which we have already discussed, 
a rather arbitrary hypothesis and extended the latter, in 1746, to all 
kinds of motions. He defined action^ following LEIBNIZ, as the product 
of mass into the velocity and the distance travelled, and he put 
forward the universal principle that this quantity is a minimum for 
the actual motion. He never gave a satisfactory proof of his principle 
(which is not surprising as it is incorrect) but defended it by meta- 
physical arguments based on the economy of nature. He was 
violently attacked, by CHEVALIER D'ARCY in Paris, SAMUEL KONIG 
from Bern and others who showed that if MAUPERTUIS' principle 
were true, thrifty nature would be forced in certain circumstances 
to spend not a minimum but a maximum of action. EULER, whose 
principle is quite correct, behaved rather strangely; he did not 
claim his own rights but even expressed his admiration for MAU- 
PERTUIS' principle which he declared to be more general. The 
reasons for this attitude are difficult to trace. One of them seems to 
be the publication by KONIG of a fragment of an alleged letter of 
LEIBNIZ in which the principle was enunciated. The genuineness of 
this letter could never be proved and it seems probable that it was 
a forgery designed to weaken MAUPERTUIS' position. This may have 
brought EULER over to the side of MAUPERTUIS who was at this 
time President of the Berlin Academy and a special favourite of the 
KING FREDERIC II, later known as the Great. The dispute was now 
carried over into the sphere of the court of Sanssouci and even into 
the arena of politics. VOLTAIRE, friend of Frederic, who heartily 
disliked the haughty President of the Academy, took the side of the 
'underdog', KONIG, and wrote a caustic pamphlet, c Dr. Akakia', 
against MAUPERTUIS. But the King, although he thoroughly enjoyed 
VOLTAIRE'S witty satire, could not sacrifice his grand President and 
was compelled to defend MAUPERTUIS. This led at last to the 
disruption of their friendship and to VOLTAIRE'S flight from Berlin, 
as described in many biographies of Frederic and of VOLTAIRE. 

The curse of confusion has rested for a long period on the principle 
of least action. LAGRANGE, whose work was the culmination of the 
development of NEWTON'S dynamics, gives an unsatisfactory formu- 
lation of the principle. JAGOBI restricts it in such a way that the 
minimum condition determines the orbit correctly; the motion in 
the orbit must be found with the help of the energy equation. This 
was an important step. But the spell was at last broken by the great 
Irishman, Sir WILLIAM ROWAN HAMILTON, whose principle is 
mathematically absolutely correct, simple and general. At the same 
time it put an end to the interpretation of the principle expressing 



74 CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 

the economy of nature. Let us look quite briefly at the real situation. 

We have already considered the quantity called potential energy of 
a set offerees, which is the amount of work which must be done to 
bring the mechanical system into a given configuration and there- 
fore represents a measure of the ability of the system to do work. 
This potential energy depends only on the configuration and has its 
minimum in the equilibrium position. If the system is in motion 
part of the potential energy is converted into energy of motion or 
kinetic energy, namely the sum of half the mass into the square of the 
velocity of the particles. The law of conservation of energy states 
that the sum of the two forms of energy is always constant. Now the 
principle of Hamilton has to do not with the sum but with the 
difference of these two kinds of energy. It states that the law of 
motion is such that a quantity frequently called action, namely the 
sum of the contributions of each time interval to the difference of 
kinetic and potential energy, is stationary for the actual motion, as 
compared with all virtual motions starting at a given time from a 
given configuration and arriving at a given subsequent time at 
another given configuration. 

Purposely I say stationary, not minimum, for indeed there is in 
general no minimum. 

What really happens can be explained very clearly with the help 
of the simple pendulum. For there is, by a kind of fortunate mathe- 
matical coincidence, a statical problem for which the genuine 
minimum principle for the potential energy coincides formally 
with the principle of least action for the pendulum. This is our old 
friend the steel tape. In fact, the sum of the bending energy of the 
weight attached is exactly the same mathematical expression as the 
total action of the pendulum (the sum of the contributions of all 
time elements to the difference of kinetic and potential energy) ; 
therefore, the curves representing the angle of inclination of the 
elastic line as a function of the distance from the free end are exactly 
the same lines as those representing the angle of deflection of the 
pendulum as a function of time. You see the vibrational character 
in the graph although only a small part of the curve is drawn. 

Now we have seen that only those regions of the graph, which 
are simply covered by the lines, correspond to a real minimum, a 
stable configuration of the elastic line. There are other regions, 
those beyond the envelope, where two or more lines pass a given 
point. Only one of those lines corresponds to a real minimum. But 
both represent possible motions of the pendulum. Although the 
conditions at the ends of the elastic tape do not correspond exactly 
to those at the ends of the time interval in HAMILTON'S principle, 



CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 75 

there is this fact in common. If the length of the tape, or the corres- 
ponding time interval in HAMILTON'S principle for the pendulum 
exceeds a certain limit, there is more than one possible solution, and 
not each of them can correspond to a true minimum, though to a 
possible motion. In this way we come to the conclusion that the 
actual motion is not in every case distinguished by a genuine 
extremal property of action, but by the fact that the action is 
stationary as explained at the beginning of the lecture. 

Thus the interpretation in terms of economy breaks down. Jf 
nature has a purpose expressed by the principle of least action it is 
certainly not anything comparable with that of a business man. We 
may, I think, regard the idea of finding purpose and economy in 
natural laws as an absurd piece of anthropomorphism, a relic of a 
time when metaphysical thinking dominated science. Even if we 
accept the idea that nature is so thrifty with her stock of action that 
she tried to save it as long as possible she succeeds, as we have 
seen, only during the first small part of the motion we cannot help 
wondering why she considers just this strange quantity as especially 
valuable. 

The importance of HAMILTON'S principle lies in a different direction 
altogether. 

It is not nature that is economical but science. All our knowledge starts 
with collecting facts, but proceeds by summarizing numerous facts 
by simple laws, and these again by more general laws. This process 
is very obvious in physics. We may recall, for instance, MAXWELL'S 
electromagnetic theory of light by which optics became a branch of 
general electrodynamics. The minimum principles are a very power- 
fill means to this end of unification. This is easily understood by 
considering the simplest example, that of the shortest path. If a 
military commander has a good map he can move his troops from 
one given point to another by simply announcing the point of 
destination, without caring much about the details of the route, 
since he supposes that the officer of the detachment will always 
march by the shortest route. This minimum principle, together 
with the map, regulates all possible movements. In the same way 
the minimum principles of physics replace innumerable special laws 
and rules always supposing the map, or in this case the kinetic 
and potential energy, are given. 

The ideal would be to condense all laws into a single law, a 
universal formula, the existence of which was postulated more than a 
century ago by the great French astronomer LAPLACE. 

If we follow the Viennese philosopher, ERNST MAGH, we must 
consider economy of thought as the only justification of science. I 



76 CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 

do not share this view; I believe that there are many other aspects 
and justifications of science but I do not deny that economy of 
thought and condensation of the results are very important, and I 
consider LAPLACE'S universal formula as a legitimate ideal. There is 
no question that the Hamiltonian principle is the adequate formula- 
tion of this tendency. It would be the universal formula if only the 
correct expressions for the potential energy of all forces were known. 
Nineteenth century thinkers believed, more or less explicitly, in this 
programme and it was successful in an amazing degree. 

By choosing a proper expression for the potential energy nearly 
all phenomena could be described, including not only the dynamics 
of rigid and elastic bodies but also that of fluids and gases, as well 



FIG. 15. 

as electricity and magnetism, together with electronic theory and 
optics. The culmination of this development was EINSTEIN'S theory 
of relativity, by which the abstract principle of least action regained 
a simple geometrical interpretation, at least that part of it depending 
on the kinetic energy. For this purpose one has to consider time as a 
fourth co-ordinate, as Fig. 15 shows (where one dimension of space 
is omitted) ; a motion is then represented by a line in this 4-dimen- 
sional world in which a non-euclidean geometry is valid, of the 
type invented by RIEMANN. The length of this line between two 
points is just the kinetic part of the action in HAMILTON'S principle, 
and the lines representing motions (under the action of gravity) are 
geodesies of the 4-dimensional space. EINSTEIN'S law of gravitation, 
which contains NEWTON'S law as a limiting case, can also be derived 
from an extremum principle in which the quantity which is an 
extremum can be interpreted as the total curvature of the space- 
time world. But these are abstract considerations on which I cannot 
dwell here. 



CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 77 

We call this period of physics, which ends with the theory of 
relativity, the classical period in contrast to the recent period which 
is dominated by the quantum theory. 

The study of atoms, their decomposition into nuclei and electrons, 
and the disintegration of the nuclei themselves has led to the convic- 
tion that the laws of classical physics do not hold down to these 
minute dimensions. A new mechanics has been developed which 
explains the observed facts very satisfactorily but deviates widely 
from classical conceptions and methods. It gives up strict deter- 
minism and replaces it by a statistical standpoint. Consider as an 
example the spontaneous disintegration of a radium atom; we 
cannot predict when it will explode but we can establish exact laws 
for the probability of the explosion, and therefore predict the 
average effects of a great number of radium atoms. The new 
mechanics assumes that all laws of physics are of this statistical 
character. The fundamental quantity is a wave function which obeys 
laws similar to those of acoustical or optical waves; it is not, how- 
ever, an observable quantity but determines indirectly the prob- 
ability of observable processes. The point which interests us here is 
the fact that even this abstract wave function of quantum mechanics 
satisfies an extremum principle of the Hamiltonian type. 

We are still far from knowing LAPLACE'S universal formula but 
we may be convinced that it will have the form of an extremal 
principle, not because nature has a will or purpose or economy, but 
because the mechanism of our thinking has no other way of 
condensing a complicated structure of laws into a short expression. 

APPENDIX 

As the argument against the economic interpretation of the principle 
of least action rests on the comparison of the dynamical problem of 
the pendulum and the statical problem of the loaded elastic tape, 
readers who know some mathematics may welcome a few formulae 
showing the identity of the variational principles for these two 
examples. 

If / is the length of the string, and 6 is the angle of deflection, 
(Fig. 1 5 A) then-j- is the angular and -7- the linear velocity; there- 

(///5\ 
I 2 where m is the mass of the 

bob. The height of the bob above its lowest position is, as the figure 
shows, / I cos 6. Multiplying this by the weight mg (g acceleration 



7& CAtSE, PUfcPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 

of gravity) we get the potential energy; but as a constant does not 
matter we can omit mgl and write the potential energy U = mgl 
cos 6. The difference of kinetic and potential energy is T U 

= 772/2 j I* + mgl cos 6, and the action during the time interval 
\dt) 

i* ( fsifi\ ~\ 

from t = o to t = r is I -I \A ( ] + W cos 6 \ dt> where the 
J I \dtj J 

o 

abbreviations A = ml 2 and W = mgl are used. 

We now consider the elastic tape. The energy stored up in the 
element ds of the tape by bending it into a curve of radius of 




FIG 16. 

curvature p is \A ds, where A is the bending modulus. The figure 

(153) shows that ds = pd0 } so that the bending energy of ds is \A 

i 

( | 2 ds, and the total elastic energy of bending %A [ } ds 9 
\dsj J \ds J 

o 

where I is the length of the tape. 

The potential energy of the weight W attached to the end is Wh 

where A is the height of this weight above the level of the clamped 

end. The figure (150) shows that h consists of contributions cos 

ds of the single elements of the tape; therefore the potential energy 

/ 

of the weight is W cos 6 ds . Adding these two potential energies 

o 

we get 



CAUSE, PURPOSE AND ECONOMY IN NATURAL LAWS 79 



an expression which is identical with the action of the pendulum if 
the element ds and the total length I of the tape are replaced by the 
time element dt and the total time r in the case of the pendulum. 



EINSTEIN'S STATISTICAL THEORIES 

[First published in Vol. VII of The Library of Living Philosophers', Albert 
Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, 1949.] 

ONE of the most remarkable volumes in the whole of scientific 
literature seems to me Vol. 17 (4th series) ofAnnalen der Physik, 
1905. It contains three papers by EINSTEIN, each dealing with a 
different subject, and each to-day acknowledged to be a master- 
piece, the source of a new branch of physics. These three subjects, 
in order of pages, are: theory of photons, Brownian motion, and 
relativity. 

Relativity is the last one, and this shows that EINSTEIN'S mind at 
that time was not completely absorbed by his ideas on space and 
time, simultaneity and electro-dynamics. In my opinion he would 
be one of the greatest theoretical physicists of all times even if he 
had not written a single line on relativity an assumption for which 
I have to apologize, as it is rather absurd. For EINSTEIN'S conception 
of the physical world cannot be divided into watertight compart- 
ments, and it is impossible to imagine that he should have by-passed 
one of the fundamental problems of the time. 

Here I propose to discuss EINSTEIN'S contributions to statistical 
methods in physics. His publications on this subject can be divided 
into two groups: an early set of papers deals with classical statistical 
mechanics, whereas the rest is connected with quantum theory. 
Both groups are intimately connected with EINSTEIN'S philosophy of 
science. He has seen more clearly than anyone before him the 
statistical background of the laws of physics, and he was a pioneer 
in the struggle for conquering the wilderness of quantum phenomena. 
Yet later, when out of his own work a synthesis of statistical and 
quantum principles emerged which seemed to be acceptable to 
almost all physicists, he kept himself aloof and sceptical. Many of 
us regard this as a tragedy for him, as he gropes his way in lone- 
liness, and for us who miss our leader and standard-bearer. I shall 
not try to suggest a resolution of this discord. We have to accept the 
fact that even in physics fundamental convictions are prior to 
reasoning, as in all other human activities. It is my task to give an 
account of EINSTEIN'S work and to discuss it from my own philoso- 
phical standpoint. 

EINSTEIN'S first paper of 1902, 'Kinetische Theorie des Warme- 
gleichgewichtes und des zweiten Hauptsatzes der Thermodynamik' 1 

80 



EINSTEIN'S STATISTICAL THEORIES 81 

is a remarkable example of the fact that when the time is ripe 
important ideas are developed almost simultaneously by different 
men at distant places. EINSTEIN says in his introduction that nobody 
has yet succeeded in deriving the conditions of thermal equilibrium 
and of the second law of thermodynamics from probability con- 
siderations, although MAXWELL and BOLTZMANN came near to it. 
WILLAKD GIBBS is not mentioned. In fact, EINSTEIN'S paper is a 
re-discovery of all essential features of statistical mechanics and 
obviously written in total ignorance of the fact that the whole 
matter had been thoroughly treated by GIBBS a year before (1901). 
The similarity is quite amazing. Like GIBBS, EINSTEIN investigates 
the statistical behaviour of a virtual assembly of equal mechanical 
systems of a very general type. A state of the single system is des- 
cribed by a set of generalized co-ordinates and velocities, which 
can be represented as a point in a 2n-dimensional 'phase-space'; the 
energy is given as function of these variables. The only consequence 
of the dynamical laws used is the theorem of LIOUVTLLE according 
to which any domain in the 2w-dimensional phase-space of all co- 
ordinates and momenta preserves its volume in time. This law 
makes it possible to define regions of equal weight and to apply the 
laws of probability. In fact, EINSTEIN'S method is essentially identical 
with GIBBS' theory of canonical assemblies. In a second paper, of the 
following year, entitled 'Eine Theorie der Grundlagen der Thermo- 
dynamik,' 2 EINSTEIN builds the theory on another basis not used 
by GIBBS, namely on the consideration of a single system in course 
of time (later called ' Zeit-Gesamtheit? time assembly), and proves 
that this is equivalent to a certain virtual assembly of many systems, 
GIBBS' micro-canonical assembly. Finally, he shows that the cano- 
nical and micro-canonical distribution lead to the same physical 
consequences. 

EINSTEIN'S approach to the subject seems to me slightly less 
abstract than that of GIBBS. This is also confirmed by the fact that 
GIBBS made no striving application of his new method, while 
EINSTEIN at once proceeded to apply his theorems to a case of utmost 
importance, namely to systems of a size suited for demonstrating the 
reality of molecules and the correctness of the kinetic theory of 
matter. 

This was the theory of Brownian movement. EINSTEIN'S papers on 
this subject are now easily accessible in a little volume edited and 
supplied with notes by R. FORTH, and translated into English by 
A. D, GowpER. 3 In the first paper (1905) he sets out to show 'that 
according to the molecular-kinetic theory of heat, bodies of micro- 
scopically visible size suspended in a liquid will perform movements 



8s EINSTEIN'S STATISTICAL THEORIES 

of such magnitude that they can be easily observed in a microscope, 

on account of the molecular motion of heat,' and he adds that these 

movements are possibly identical with the 'Brownian motion' though 

his information about the latter is too vague to form a definite 

judgment. 

The fundamental step taken by EINSTEIN was the idea of raising 
the kinetic theory of matter from a possible, plausible, useful 
hypothesis to a matter of observation, by pointing out cases where 
the molecular motion and its statistical character can be made 
visible. It was the first example of a phenomenon of thermal fluctua- 
tions, and his method is the classical paradigma for the treatment 
of all of them. He regards the movement of the suspended particles 
as a process of diffusion under the action of osmotic pressure and 
other forces, among which friction due to the viscosity of the liquid 
is the most important one. The logical clue to the understanding of 
the phenomenon consists in the statement that the actual velocity 
of the suspended particle, produced by the impacts of the molecules 
of the liquid on it, is unobservable; the visible effect in a finite 
interval of time r consists of irregular displacements, the probability 
of which satisfies a differential equation of the same type as the 
equation of diffusion. The diffusion coefficient is nothing but the 
mean square of the displacement divided by ar. In this way EINSTEIN 
obtained his celebrated law expressing the mean square displace- 
ment for T in terms of measurable quantities (temperature, radius 
of the particle, viscosity of the liquid) and of the number of mole- 
cules in a gramme-molecule (AVOGADRO'S number JV). By its 
simplicity and clarity this paper is a classic of our science. 

In the second paper (1906) EINSTEIN refers to the work of SEDEN- 
TOPF (Jena) and GOUY (Lyon) who convinced themselves by 
observations that the Brownian motion was in fact caused by the 
thermal agitation of the molecules of the liquid, and from this 
moment on he takes it for granted that the 'irregular motion of 
suspended particles' predicted by him is identical with the Brownian 
motion. This and the following publications are devoted to the 
working out of details (e.g. rotatory Brownian motion) and presenting 
the theory in other forms; but they contain nothing essentially new. 

I think that these investigations of EINSTEIN have done more than 
any other work to convince physicists of the reality of atoms and 
molecules, of the kinetic theory of heat, and of the fundamental 
part of probability in the natural laws. Reading these papers one 
is inclined to believe that at that time the statistical aspect of physics 
was preponderant in EINSTEIN'S mind; yet at the same time he 
worked on relativity where rigorous causality reigns. His conviction 



EINSTEIN'S STATISTICAL THEORIES 83 

seems always to have been, and still is to-day, that the ultimate laws 
of nature are causal and deterministic, that probability is used to 
cover our ignorance if we have to do with numerous particles, and 
that only the vastness of this ignorance pushes statistics into the 
forefront. 

Most physicists do not share this view to-day, and the reason for 
this is the development of quantum theory. EINSTEIN'S contribution 
to this development is great. His first paper of 1905, mentioned 
already, is usually quoted for the interpretation of the photo- 
electric effect and similar phenomena (STORES' law of photo- 
luminescence, photo-ionisation) in terms of light-quanta (light-darts, 
photons). As a matter of fact, the main argument of EINSTEIN is 
again of a statistical nature, and the phenomena just mentioned are 
used in the end for confirmation. This statistical reasoning is very 
characteristic of EINSTEIN, and produces the impression that for him 
the laws of probability are central and more important by far 
than any other law. He starts with the fundamental difference 
between an ideal gas and a cavity filled with radiation: the gas 
consists of a finite number of particles, while radiation is described 
by a set of functions in space, hence by an infinite number of 
variables. This is the root of the difficulty of explaining the law of 
black body radiation; the monochromatic density of radiation turns 
out to be proportional to the absolute temperature (later known as 
the law of RAYLEIGH-JEANS) with a factor independent of frequency, 
and therefore the total density becomes infinite. In order to avoid 
this, PLANCK (1900) had introduced the hypothesis that radiation 
consists of quanta of finite size. EINSTEIN, however, does not use 
PLANCK'S radiation law, but the simpler law of WEEN, which is the 
limiting case for low radiation density, expecting rightly that here 
the corpuscular character of the radiation will be more evident. He 
shows how one can obtain the entropy S of black body radiation 
from a given radiation law (monochromatic density as function of 
frequency) and applies then BOLTZMANN'S fundamental relation 
between entropy S and thermodynamic probability W, 



where A; is the gas constant per molecule, for determining W '. This 
formula was certainly meant by BOLTZMANN to express the physical 
quantity S in terms of the combinatory quantity W, obtained by 
counting all possible configurations of the atomistic elements of the 
statistical ensemble. EINSTEIN inverts this process: he starts from the 
known function S in order to obtain an expression for the probability 
which can be used as a clue to the interpretation of the statistical 



84 EINSTEIN'S STATISTICAL THEORIES 

elements. (The same trick has been applied by him later in his work 
on fluctuations ; 4 although this is of considerable practical importance, 
I shall only mention it, since it introduces no new fundamental 
concept apart from that 'inversion'.) 

Substituting the entropy derived from WIEN'S law into BOLTZ- 
MANN'S formula, EINSTEIN obtains for the probability of finding the 
total energy E by chance compressed in a fraction aV of the total 
volume V W = a, E *; 

that means, the radiation behaves as if it consisted of independent 
quanta of energy of size hv and number n E\hv. It is obvious from 
the text of the paper that this result had an overwhelming power of 
conviction for EINSTEIN, and that it led him to search for confirma- 
tion of a more direct kind. This he found in the physical phenomena 
mentioned above (e.g. photoelectric effect) whose common feature 
is the exchange of energy between an electron and light. The 
impression produced on the experimentalists by these discoveries 
was very great. For the facts were known to many, but not correlated. 
At that time EINSTEIN'S gift for divining such correlations was almost 
uncanny. It was based on a thorough knowledge of experimental 
facts combined with a profound understanding of the present state 
of theory, which enabled him to see at once where something 
strange was happening. His work at that period was essentially 
empirical in method, though directed to building up a consistent 
theory in contrast to his later work when he was more and more 
led by philosophical and mathematical ideas. 

A second example of the application of this method is the work 
on specific heat. 6 It started again with a theoretical consideration 
of that type which provided the strongest evidence in EINSTEIN'S 
mind, namely on statistics. He remarks that PLANCK'S radiation 
formula can be understood by giving up the continuous distribution 
of statistical weight in the phase-space which is a consequence of 
LIOUVILLE'S theorem of dynamics; instead, for vibrating systems of 
the kind used as absorbers and emitters in the theory of radiation 
most states have a vanishing statistical weight and only a selected 
number (whose energies are multiples of a quantum) have finite 
weights. 

Now if this is so, the quantum is not a feature of radiation but of 
general physical statistics, and should therefore appear in other 
phenomena where vibrators are involved. This argument was 
obviously the moving force in EINSTEIN'S mind, and it became fertile 
by his knowledge of facts and his unfailing judgment of their bearing 
on the problem. I wonder whether he knew that there were solid 



EINSTEIN'S STATISTICAL THEORIES 85 

elements for which the specific heat per mole was lower than its 
normal value 5-94 calories, given by the law of DULONG-PETTT, or 
whether he first had the theory and then scanned the tables to find 
examples. The law of DULONG-PETIT is a direct consequence of the 
law of equipartition of classical statistical mechanics, which states 
that each co-ordinate or momentum contributing a quadratic term 
to the energy should carry the same average energy, namely \ RT 
per mole where R is the gas constant; as R is a little less than 2 
calories per degree and an oscillator has 3 co-ordinates and 3 
momenta, the energy of one mole of a solid element per degree of 
temperature should be 6 X %R, or 5-94 calories. If there are 
substances for which the experimental value is essentially lower, as 
it actually is for carbon (diamond), boron, silicon, one has a 
contradiction between facts and classical theory. Another such 
contradiction is provided by some substances with poly-atomic 
molecules. DRUDE had proved by optical experiments that the 
atoms in these molecules were performing oscillations about each 
other; hence the number of vibrating units per molecule should be 
higher than 6 and therefore the specific heat higher than the 
DULONG-PETIT value but that is not always the case. Moreover 
EINSTEIN could not help wondering about the contribution of the 
electrons to the specific heat. At that time vibrating electrons in 
the atom were assumed for explaining the ultra-violet absorption; 
they apparently did not contribute to the specific heat, in contradic- 
tion to the equipartition law. 

All these difficulties were at once swept away by EINSTEIN'S 
suggestion that the atomic oscillators do not follow the equipartition 
law, but the same law which leads to PLANCK'S radiation formula. 
Then the mean energy would not be proportional to the absolute 
temperature but decrease more quickly with falling temperature in 
a way which still depends on the frequencies of the oscillators. High 
frequency oscillators like the electrons would at ordinary tempera- 
ture contribute nothing to the specific heat, atoms only if they were 
not too light and not too strongly bound. EINSTEIN confirmed that 
these conditions were satisfied for the cases of poly-atomic molecules 
for which DRUDE had estimated the frequencies, and he showed that 
the measurements of the specific heat of diamond agreed fairly well 
with his calculation. 

But this is not the place to enter into a discussion of the physical 
details of EINSTEIN'S discovery. The consequences with regard to the 
principles of scientific knowledge were far-reaching. It was now 
proved that the quantum effects were not a specific property of 
radiation but a general feature of physical systems. The old rule 



86 EINSTEIN'S STATISTICAL THEORIES 

'natura non facit saltus* was disproved: there are fundamental dis- 
continuities, quanta of energy, not only in radiation but in ordinary 
matter. 

In EINSTEIN'S model of a molecule or a solid these quanta are 
still closely connected with the motion of single vibrating particles. 
But soon it became clear that a considerable generalization was 
necessary. The atoms in molecules and crystals are not independent 
but coupled by strong forces. Therefore the motion of an individual 
particle is not that of a single harmonic oscillator, but the super- 
position of many harmonic vibrations. The carrier of a simple 
harmonic motion is nothing material at all ; it is the abstract 'normal 
mode', well known from ordinary mechanics. For crystals in particu- 
lar each normal mode is a standing wave. The introduction of this 
idea opened the way to a quantitative theory of thermodynamics of 
molecules and crystals and demonstrated the abstract character of 
the new quantum physics which began to emerge from this work. It 
became clear that the laws of micro-physics differed fundamentally 
from those of matter in bulk. Nobody has done more to elucidate 
this than EINSTEIN. I cannot report all his contributions, but shall 
confine myself to two outstanding investigations which paved the 
way for the new micro-mechanics which physics at large has 
accepted to-day while EINSTEIN himself stands aloof, critical, 
sceptical, and hoping that this episode may pass by and physics 
return to classical principles. 

The first of these two investigations has again to do with the law 
of radiation and statistics. 6 There are two ways of tackling problems 
of statistical equilibrium. The first is a direct one, which one may 
call the combinatory method: After having established the weights 
of elementary cases one calculates the number of combinations of 
these elements which correspond to an observable state; this number 
is the statistical probability W, from which all physical properties 
can be obtained (e.g. the entropy by BOLTZMANN'S formula). The 
second method consists in determining the rates of all competing 
elementary processes, which lead to the equilibrium in question. 
This is, of course, much more difficult; for it demands not only the 
counting of equally probable cases but a real knowledge of the 
mechanism involved. But, on the other hand, it carries much further, 
providing not only the conditions of equilibrium but also of the 
time-rate of processes starting from non-equilibrium configurations. 
A classical example of this second method is BOLTZMANN'S and 
MAXWELL'S formulation of the kinetic theory of gases; here the 
elementary mechanism is given by binary encounters of molecules, 
the rate of which is proportional to the number-density of both 



EINSTEIN'S STATISTICAL THEORIES 87 

partners. From the 'collision equation 9 the distribution function of 
the molecules can be determined not only in statistical equilibrium, 
but also for the case of motion in bulk, flow of heat, diffusion, etc. 
Another example is the law of mass-action in chemistry, established 
by GULDBERG and WAAGE; here again the elementary mechanism 
is provided by multiple collisions of groups of molecules which 
combine, split, or exchange atoms at a rate proportional to the 
number-density of the partners. A special case of these elementary 
processes is the monatomic reaction, where the molecules of one 
type spontaneously explode with a rate proportional to their 
number-density. This case has a tremendous importance in nuclear 
physics: it is the law of radio-active decay. Whereas in the few 
examples of ordinary chemistry, where monatomic reaction has 
been observed, a dependence of reaction velocity on the physical 
conditions (e.g. temperature) could be assumed or even observed, 
this was not the case for radio-activity: the decay constant seemed to 
be an invariable property of the nucleus, unchangeable by any 
external influences. Each individual nucleus explodes at an un- 
predictable moment; yet if a great number of nuclei are observed, 
the average rate of disintegration is proportional to the total number 
present. It looks as if the law of causality is put out of action for 
these processes. 

Now what EINSTEIN did was to show that PLANCK'S law of radia- 
tion can just be reduced to processes of a similar type, of a more or 
less non-causal character. Consider two stationary states of an atom, 
say the lowest state i and an excited state a. EINSTEIN assumes that 
if an atom is found to be in the state 2 it has a certain probability of 
returning to the ground state i, emitting a photon of a frequency 
which, according to the quantum law, corresponds to the energy 
difference between the two states; i.e. in a big assembly of such 
atoms the number of atoms in state 2 returning to the ground state i 
per unit time is proportional to their initial number exactly as 
for radio-active disintegration. The radiation, on the other hand, 
produces a certain probability for the reverse process i -> 2 which 
represents absorption of a photon of frequency v 12 and is propor- 
tional to the radiation density for the frequency. 

Now these two processes alone balancing one another would not 
lead to PLANCK'S formula; EINSTEIN is compelled to introduce a 
third one, namely an influence of the radiation on the emission 
process 2 i, 'induced emission,' which again has a probability 
proportional to the radiation density for v ia . 

This extremely simple argument together with the most elementary 
principle of BOLTZMANN'S statistics leads at once to PLANCK'S 



Qg EINSTEIN*S STATISTICAL THEORIES 

formula without any specification of the magnitude of the transition 
probabilities. EINSTEIN has connected it with a consideration of the 
transfer of momentum between atom and radiation, showing that 
the mechanism proposed by him is not consistent with the classical 
idea of spherical waves but only with a dart-like behaviour of the 
quanta. Here we are not concerned with this side of EINSTEIN'S 
work, but with its bearing on his attitude to the fundamental 
question of causal and statistical laws in physics. From this point of 
view this paper is of particular interest. For it meant a decisive step 
in the direction of non-causal, indeterministic reasoning. Of course, 
I am sure that EINSTEIN himself was and is still convinced that 
there are structural properties in the excited atom which determine 
the exact moment of emission, and that probability is called in only 
because of our incomplete knowledge of the pre-history of the atom. 
Yet the fact remains that he has initiated the spreading of indeter- 
ministic statistical reasoning from its original source, radio-activity, 
into other domains of physics. 

Still another feature of EINSTEIN'S work must be mentioned which 
was also of considerable assistance to the formulation of indeter- 
ministic physics in quantum mechanics. It is the fact that it follows 
from the validity of PLANCK'S law of radiation that the probabilities 
of absorption (i -> 2) and induced emission (2 -> i) are equal. This 
was the first indication that interaction of atomic systems always 
involves two states in a symmetrical way. In classical mechanics an 
external agent like radiation acts on one definite state, and the 
result of the action can be calculated from the properties of this 
state and the external agent. In quantum mechanics each process is 
a transition between two states which enter symmetrically into the 
laws of interaction with an external agent. This symmetrical 
property was one of the deciding clues which led to the formulation 
of matrix mechanics, the earliest form of modern quantum mechan- 
ics. The first indication of this symmetry was provided by EINSTEIN'S 
discovery of the equality of up- and down-ward transition proba- 
bilities. 

The last of EINSTEIN'S investigations which I wish to discuss in 
this report is his work on the quantum theory of monatomic ideal 
gases. 7 In this case the original idea was not his but came from an 
Indian physicist, S. N. BOSE; his paper appeared in a translation by 
EmsTEDsr 8 himself who added a remark that he regarded this work 
as an important progress. The essential point in Boss's procedure is 
that he treats photons like particles of a gas with the method of 
statistical mechanics but with the difference that these particles are 
not distinguishable. He does not distribute individual particles over 



EINSTEIN'S STATISTICAL THEORIES 89 

a set of states, but counts the number of states which contain a given 
number of particles. This combinatory process together with the 
physical conditions (given number of states and total energy) leads 
at once to PLANCK'S radiation law. EINSTEIN added to this idea the 
suggestion that the same process ought to be applied to material 
atoms in order to obtain the quantum theory of a monatomic gas. 
The deviation from the ordinary gas laws derived from this theory 
is called 'gas degeneracy.' EINSTEIN'S papers appeared just a year 
before the discovery of quantum mechanics ; one of them contains 
moreover (p. 9 of the second paper) a reference to DE BROGLIE'S 
celebrated thesis, and the remark that a scalar wave field can be 
associated with a gas. These papers of DE BROGLIE and EINSTEIN 
stimulated SCHRODINGER to develop his wave mechanics, as he 
himself confessed at the end of his famous paper. 9 It was the same 
remark of EINSTEIN'S which a year or two later formed the link 
between DE BROGLIE'S theory and the experimental discovery of 
electron diffraction; for, when DAVTSSON sent me his results on the 
strange maxima found in the reflexion of electrons by crystals, I 
remembered EINSTEIN'S hint and directed ELSASSER to investigate 
whether those maxima could be interpreted as interference fringes 
of DE BROGLIE waves. EINSTEIN is therefore clearly involved in the 
foundation of wave mechanics, and no alibi can disprove it. 

I cannot see how the BOSE-EINSTEIN counting of equally probable 
cases can be justified without the conceptions of quantum mechanics. 
There a state of equal particles is described not by noting their 
individual positions and momenta, but by a symmetric wave function 
containing the co-ordinates as arguments; this represents clearly 
only one state and has to be counted once. A group of equal particles 
even if they are perfectly alike, can still be distributed between two 
boxes in many ways you may not be able to distinguish th.em 
individually but that does not affect their being individuals. Al- 
though arguments of this kind are more metaphysical than physical, 
the use of a symmetric wave function as representation of a state 
seems to me preferable. This way of thinking has, moreover, led to 
the other case of gas degeneracy, discovered by FERMI and DIRAG, 
where the wave function is skew, and to a host of physical conse- 
quences confirmed by experiment. 

The BOSE-EINSTEIN statistics was, to my knowledge, EINSTEIN'S 
last decisive positive contribution to physical statistics. His following 
work in this line, though of great importance by stimulating thought 
and discussion, was essentially critical. He refused to acknowledge 
the claim of quantum mechanics to have reconciled the particle 
and wave aspects of radiation. This claim is based on a complete 



go EINSTEIN'S STATISTICAL THEORIES 

re-orientation of physical principles : causal laws are replaced by 
statistical ones, determinism by indeterminism. I have tried to show 
that EINSTEIN himself has paved the way for this attitude. Yet some 
principle of his philosophy forbids him to follow it to the end. What 
is this principle? 

EINSTEIN'S philosophy is not a system which you can read in a 
book; you have to take the trouble to abstract it from his papers on 
physics and from a few more general articles and pamphlets. I have 
found no definite statement of his about the question 'What is 
Probability?'; nor has he taken part in the discussions going on 
about VON MISES' definition and other such endeavours. I suppose 
he would have dismissed them as metaphysical speculation, or even 
joked about them. From the beginning he has used probability as 
a tool for dealing with nature just like any scientific device. He has 
certainly very strong convictions about the value of these tools. His 
attitude toward philosophy and epistemology is well described in 
his obituary article on ERNST MAGH: IQ 

Nobody who devotes himself to science from other reasons than super- 
ficial ones, like ambition, money making, or the pleasure of brain-sport, 
can neglect the questions, what are the aims of science, how far are its 
general results true, what is essential and what based on accidental features 
of the development? 

Later in the same article he formulates his empirical creed in these 
words: 

Concepts which have been proved to be useful in ordering things easily 
acquire such an authority over us that we forget their human origin and 
accept them as invariable. Then they become 'necessities of thought,' 
'given a priori? etc. The path of scientific progress is then, by such errors, 
barred for a long time. It is therefore no useless game if we are insisting 
on analysing current notions and pointing out on what conditions their 
justification and usefulness depends, especially how they have grown from 
the data of experience. In this way their exaggerated authority is broken. 
They are removed, if they cannot properly legitimate themselves; corrected, 
if their correspondence to the given things was too negligently established; 
replaced by others, if a new system can be developed that we prefer for 
good reasons. 

That is the core of the young EINSTEIN, thirty years ago. I am sure 
the principles of probability were then for him of the same kind as 
all other concepts used for describing nature, so impressively 
formulated in the lines above. The EINSTEIN of to-day is changed. I 
translate here a passage of a letter from him which I received about 
four years ago (November yth, 1944) : In our scientific expectation 
we have grown antipodes. You believe in God playing dice and I 
in perfect laws in the world of things existing as real objects, which 
I try to grasp in a wildly speculative way.' These speculations 



EINSTEIN'S srAtisncAL THEORIES gi 

distinguish indeed his present work from his earlier writings. But if 
any man has the right to speculate it is he whose fundamental results 
stand like a rock. What he is aiming at is a general field-theory which 
preserves the rigid causality of classical physics and restricts proba- 
bility to masking our ignorance of the initial conditions or, if you 
prefer, of the pre-history, of all details of the system considered. 
This is not the place to argue about the possibility of achieving 
this. Yet I wish to make one remark, using EINSTEIN'S own picturesque 
language : If God has made the world a perfect mechanism, he has 
at least conceded so much to our imperfect intellect that, in order 
to predict little parts of it, we need not solve innumerable differential 
equations but can use dice with fair success. That this is so I have 
learned, with many of my contemporaries, from EINSTEIN himself. 
I think, this situation has not changed much by the introduction of 
quantum statistics; it is still we mortals who are playing dice for 
our little purposes of prognosis God's actions are as mysterious in 
classical Brownian motion as in radio-activity and quantum radia- 
tion, or in life at large. 

EINSTEIN'S dislike of modern physics has not only been expressed 
in general terms, which can be answered in a similarly general and 
vague way, but also in very substantial papers in which he has 
formulated objections against definite statements of wave mechanics. 
The best known paper of this kind is one published in collaboration 
with PODOLSKY and RosEN. 11 That it goes very deep into the logical 
foundations of quantum mechanics is apparent from the reactions it 
has evoked. NIELS BOHR has answered in detail; SCHRODINGER has 
published his own sceptical views on the interpretation of quantum 
mechanics; REICHENBACH deals with this problem in the last 
chapter of his excellent book. Philosophic Foundations of Quantum 
Mechanics, and shows that a complete treatment of the difficulties 
pointed out by EINSTEIN, PODOLSKY, and ROSEN needs an overhaul 
of logic itself. He introduces a three-valued logic, in which apart 
from the truth-values c true s and 'false', there is an intermediate one, 
called 'indeterminate', or, in other words, he rejects the old principle 
of 'tertium non datur\ as has been proposed long before, from purely 
mathematical reasons, by BROUWER and other mathematicians. I 
am not a logician, and in such disputes always trust that expert 
who last talked to me. My attitude to statistics in quantum mechanics 
is hardly affected by formal logic, and I venture to say that the 
same holds for EINSTEIN. That his opinion in this matter differs 
from mine is regrettable, but it is no object of logical dispute between 
us. It is based on different experience in our work and life. But in 
spite of this, he remains my beloved master. 



92 EINSTEIN'S STATISTICAL THEORIES 

REFERENCES 

A. EINSTEIN, Annalen der Physik (1902) (4), 9, p. 477. 
A. EINSTEIN, Annalen der Physik (1903) (4), n, p. 170. 
A. EINSTEIN, Investigations on the Theory of the Brownian Movement. London: 

Methuen & Go. (1926). 

A. EINSTEIN, Annalen der Physik (1906) (4), 19, p. 373. 
A. EINSTEIN, Annalen der Physik (1907) (4), 22, p. 180. 
A. EINSTEIN, Phys. . (1917), 18, p. 121. 
A. EINSTEIN, BerL Ber. (1924) p. 261; (1925) p. 318. 
S. N. BOSE (1924) Zeitschriftfur Physik, 26, 178. 
E. SCHRODINGER, Annalen der Physik (1926) (4), 70, p. 361; s. p. 373. 

10 A. EINSTEIN, Phys. . (1916) 17, p. 101. 

11 A. EINSTEIN, B. PODOLSKY and N. ROSEN (1935) Phys. Rev., 47, 777. 



PHYSICS AND METAPHYSICS 

[Joule Memorial Lecture, 1950. First published in Vol. 91 of Memoirs and 
Proceedings of the Manchester Literary and Philosophical Society, 1049-50.] 

HpHE subject which I have chosen to commemorate the great 
* discoverer of the first law of thermodynamics has nothing to do 
with JOULE'S own work. In fact I would be quite incompetent to 
deal with experiments, and my knowledge of the history of JOULE'S 
discovery in connection with the work of his contemporaries, 
ROBERT MAYER and HELMHOLTZ, is second-hand. I propose to 
speak about a very general matter. It is on the borderline of two 
fields of research, and this seems to imply that I am familiar with 
both of them. However, though I feel on fairly stable ground when 
speaking about physics, I cannot claim in any way to be expert in 
what is customarily treated in philosophical books and lectures under 
the title of metaphysics. What I know of it is more or less the recollec- 
tion from my student days, refreshed by some sporadic reading. 
Long years of neglect have not deleted the deep impression received 
in my youth by the age-old attempts to answer the most urgent 
questions of the human mind: the questions about the ultimate 
meaning of existence, about the Universe at large and our part in it, 
about life and death, truth and error, goodness and vice, God and 
eternity. But just as deep as this impression of the importance of the 
problems is the memory of the futility of the endeavour. There 
seemed to be no steady progress as we find in the special sciences, 
and like so many others, I turned my back to philosophy and found 
satisfaction in a restricted field where problems can actually be 
solved. Yet getting old, I feel, again like many others, whose pro- 
ductive powers are declining, the desire to summarise the results of 
the scientific search in which, during several decades, I have taken 
a small part, and that leads unavoidably back to those eternal 
questions which go under the title of metaphysics. 

Let me quote two definitions of metaphysics by modern philoso- 
phers. WTT.T.TAM JAMES says: 'Metaphysics is an unusually stubborn 
effort to think dearly. 3 BERTRAND RUSSELL says: 'Metaphysics, or 
the attempt to conceive the world as a whole by means of thought/ 

These formulations stress two important aspects; one the method: 
stubborn clear thinking; the other the object: the world as a whole. 
But is every case of stubborn clear thinking metaphysics? Every 
scientist, every historian, philologist, even theologian would claim 

93 



94 PHYSICS AND METAPHYSICS 

to think clearly. On the other hand, the world as a whole is a subject 
not only vast, but definitely not closed, open to new discovery at any 
moment, therefore not exhausted and probably inexhaustible; in 
short, the world known to us is never a whole. I shall return to this 
point at the end. 

I propose to use the word metaphysics in a more modest way, 
regard to method and subject as well, namely as an investigation into 
the general features of the structure of the world and our methods 
to deal with this structure. I wish to discuss in particular the question 
whether the progress of physics has contributed anything essential 
to this problem. This progress of physics has been, as we are all 
aware, somewhat sensational during the last few years, and the aspect 
of the physical world has thoroughly changed in the half century of 
my own scientific life. Yet the methods of the physicist have always 
remained essentially the same : experimenting, observing regularities, 
formulating mathematical laws, predicting new phenomena with 
the help of these laws, combining the different empirical laws in 
coherent theories, which satisfy our sense of harmony and logical 
beauty, and testing these theories again by prediction. These succes- 
ful predictions are the highlights of theoretical physics, as we have 
witnessed in our day in the case of DE BROGUE'S waves, of DIRAC'S 
positron, YUKAWA'S meson and many more such cases. 

The power of prediction is the main claim of physics. It is based 
on the acceptance of the principle of causality, which, in its most 
general form, means the assumption of invariable laws of Nature. 
Yet you will all have heard that modern physics has been led to 
doubt this principle. Here is the first metaphysical conception on 
which I wish to make some comments. 

Closely connected with it is the conception of reality. The sceptical 
attitude in regard to causality has arisen in atomic physics where the 
objects are not immediately accessible to our senses but only in- 
directly, with the help of more or less complicated apparatus. These 
ultimate objects of physics are particles, forces, fields, etc. ; what 
kind of reality can one ascribe to them? This leads to the more 
general question of the relation between subject and object, of the 
existence of an objective physical world independent of the observing 
subject, and thus back to RUSSELL'S problem, whether a conception 
of the world as a whole is actually possible. 

The cause-effect relation is used in ordinary life in two rather 
different ways, which may be illustrated by the following two 
statements: 

'The capitalistic system is the cause of economic crises', and 'the 
economic crisis of 1930 was caused by a panic at the New York 



PHYSICS AND METAPHYSICS 95 

exchange'. One states a general rule or law, independent of time; 
the other declares one definite event to be the necessary sequence of 
another definite event. Both cases have the idea of necessity in 
common, a conception of a somewhat mysterious character which I 
feel completely unable to analyse further, and which I am willing 
to accept as metaphysical. Classical physics has officially adopted 
the second form of causality, as a necessary sequence in time. This 
came about through the discovery of the fundamental laws of 
mechanics by GALILEO and NEWTON, laws which allow the predic- 
tion of future events from previous ones or vice versa. In other 
words, these laws are deterministic: a world governed solely by 
them would be a gigantic machine; the complete knowledge of the 
situation at a given time would determine the situation at any other 
time. This kind of determinism was regarded by the physicists of the 
last century as the only rational interpretation of causality, and by 
using it they boasted that they had eliminated from physics the last 
remnants of metaphysical thinking. 

Now it seems to me that this identification of determinism and 
causality is quite arbitrary and confusing. There are deterministic 
relations which are not causal; for instance, any time table or 
programmatic statement. 

To take an absurdly obvious case, you could predict from the 
programme of a pantomime the sequence of the scenes but would 
hardly say that the acrobats of scene No. 5 had caused the love 
scene No. 6. To return to science. The Ptolemaic system of the 
Cosmos is a deterministic but not a causal interpretation, and the 
same can be said about COPERNICUS' cycles and KEPLER'S ellipses. 
They are all, in the usual scientific terminology, kinematic descrip- 
tions, but not causal explanations. For no cause of the phenomena 
is given except the ultimate cause of the creator's will. Then came 
the dynamical theories of GALILEO and NEWTON. If one sticks to the 
programme that the only aim of a theory is deterministic prediction, 
the progress made by the introduction of dynamics into astronomy 
can merely be seen in a considerable condensation and simplifica- 
tion of the laws. When I was a student in Germany, fifty years ago, 
this standpoint, skilfully formulated by KIRGHHOFF, was dominant 
and is still widely shared. 

I think that the discovery of mechanics was a much more funda- 
mental affair. GALILEO showed that a certain quantity, connected 
with the motion of a body, namely its acceleration, is independent 
of the body and of its motion and only dependent on its position 
relative to the earth; and NEWTON showed the same for the planets 
where the acceleration depends only on the distance from the sun. 



g6 PHYSICS AND METAPHYSICS 

This appears to me something more than a short and efficient 
description of facts. It means the introducing of a quantitative 
expression of the cause-effect relation in its most general form 
through the concept of force. It introduces the idea, foreign to the 
older kinematic theories, that one set of data (here positions) 
'causes' another set of data (here accelerations). The word 'causes' 
means just 'determines quantitatively', and the law offeree expresses 
in detail how the effect depends on the cause. 

This interpretation of the laws of mechanics brings them into 
line with the ordinary practice of the scientist. An experiment is 
planned, i.e. certain conditions of observation are produced; then 
the effect is observed, sometimes at a future date, but more often 
all the time while the conditions hold. It is the timeless relation 
between observation and conditions of observation (apparatus) 
which is the real object of science. I suggest that this is the actual 
meaning of the principle of causality, as distinct from determinism, 
which is a special, and almost accidental property of the mechanical 
laws (due to the fact that one kind of the quantities involved are 
accelerations, i.e. time derivatives). 

If one looks on the history of physics during the last centuries 
from this point of view (as I have tried in my Waynflete Lectures, 
which have recently been published under the title 'Natural 
Philosophy of Cause and Chance') one gets the following im- 
pression: 

Physics has used just this timeless cause-effect relation in its 
everyday practice but another notion in the theoretical interpreta- 
tion. There causality was taken as synonymous with determinism, 
and as the deterministic form of the mechanical laws is an empirical 
fact, this interpretation was hailed as a great achievement in 
eliminating dark metaphysical concepts. However, these concepts 
have a strange way of asserting themselves. Causality has in every- 
day life two attributes, which for shortness I shall call the principles 
of contiguity and of antecedence. The first states that things can act 
only on neighbouring things, or through a chain of things in con- 
tact, and the second that if cause and effect refer to situations at 
different times the cause should be prior to the effect. 

Both principles are violated by Newtonian mechanics, as the 
gravitational force acts over any distance of empty space, and as 
the laws of motion connect two configurations at different times in a 
perfectly symmetric and reversible way. One can regard the whole 
development of classical physics as a struggle to re-establish these 
two essential features of the concepts of cause and effect. The 
methods to preserve contiguity were mathematically developed, by 



PHYSICS AND METAPHYSICS 97 

CAUCHY and others, by extending mechanics to continuous media; 
the idea of contiguity played a leading part in FARADAY'S researches 
on electricity and magnetism, and led to MAXWELL'S concept of a 
field offeree propagating itself with finite velocity, which was soon 
confirmed by HERTZ'S discovery of electro-magnetic waves. Finally 
NEWTON'S case was brought into line with contiguity through 
EINSTEIN'S relativistic theory of the gravitational field. No modern 
theory of interaction is thinkable which violates this principle. 

Antecedence has a much more tortuous history and not a happy 
end. It took much effort to discover that in physics the distinction 
between past and future was linked with the irreversibility of heat 
phenomena here we remember JOULE as one of the central figures 
and to reconcile this result with the reversibility of mechanics 
through the development of atomistics and statistical methods. I 
think that this work, initiated by MAXWELL, BOLTZMANN, GIBBS 
and EINSTEIN, is one of the greatest achievements in science. The 
deterministic interpretation of causality could be maintained for 
the atomic world and yet the apparent validity of antecedence 
understood as an effect of the statistical law of large numbers. 
However, this interpretation carried the germ of self-destruction of 
one of its pillars: it opened the way to the study of the atomic world, 
and the result was that the presupposed validity of Newtonian 
mechanics in this microscopic world was wrong. The new quantum 
mechanics does not allow a deterministic interpretation, and since 
classical physics has identified causality with determinism, the doom 
of the causal explanation of nature seems to have come. 

I am much opposed to this view. It does not matter much in 
discussions between scientists who know exactly what they are 
talking about; but it is harmful if used in describing the last results 
of science to the non-scientific world. Extremes are always harmful. 
The deterministic mechanistic view produced a philosophy which 
shut its eyes against the most obvious facts of experience; but a 
philosophy which rejects not only determinism, but causation, 
altogether seems to me just as absurd. I think that there exists a 
reasonable definition of the cause-effect relation which I have 
already mentioned: that a certain situation depends on another one 
(irrespective of time) in a way describable by quantitative laws. 

I shall indicate how this is still true in quantum mechanics in 
spite of its indeterministic character, and how the apparent loss is 
compensated by another fundamental principle, called complement- 
arity, which will be of great philosophical and practical importance. 

This new conception is due to NIELS BOHR, the great Danish 
physicist, who was one of the leaders in the development of quantum 



98 PHYSICS AND METAPHYSICS 

mechanics, not only in regard to physics itself, but also to the 
philosophical implications. I was fortunate enough to listen to his 
Gifford Lectures, given in Edinburgh last autumn, which I hope 
will be published in the not too far distant future. I cannot give you 
an account of his ideas in the short time left to me, but only try to 
outline the main points and to bring them into line with my slightly 
different formulations. 

As you will know, PLANCK'S fundamental law of quantum 
theory connects an energy E with a frequency v, by the simple 
formula E = hv 9 where h is a constant. This was later extended by 
EINSTEIN and DE BROGUE, from the number of vibrations v per unit 
time to the number of waves K per unit length, which is connected 
with a mechanical momentum p by the corresponding formula 
p = kK> with the same constant h. 

That this is so, has been confirmed by innumerable direct ex- 
periments and more or less indirect inferences from observations. 
Whenever a process can be resolved in periodic components with 
definite periods in time and space, i.e. with definite v and /c, the 
effect of it on the motion of particles consists in transferring energy 
and momentum according to this law. This empirical fact must be 
accepted as undeniable before its implications can be discussed. 

Now this fact is so extremely strange that it took many years 
before physicists began to consider it seriously, and NIELS BOHR 
himself has used the word 'irrational' to describe the new feature of 
the physical world discovered by PLANCK. Why irrational ? Because 
energy and momentum of a particle are, by their definition, related 
to an extremely small region of space, practically to a point, while 
frequency and wave number, also by their definition, are related to 
a very large, theoretically infinite, extension of space and time. This 
latter point will perhaps not appear so obvious as the first; you may 
say, I hear a tone of a piano string well defined even if it is played 
extremely staccato. This is practically true, because our ear is not 
a very sensitive instrument to discover tiny distortions. But the 
telecommunication engineer is familiar with the fact that there is a 
distortion. A tone lasting only a short time, comparable with the 
period, is not pure any more but accompanied by other tones, with 
frequencies spread out over a little interval Ay around the original 
one; and if the duration is getting shorter and shorter this interval 
becomes larger and larger, until no tone is heard but a noise, a 
crack. As modern telecommunication is based on the principle of 
modulation, i.e. of interrupting a high frequency current in the 
rhythm of signals or modifying its strength according to the relatively 
slow vibrations of speech or music, it is obvious that there is a limit 



PHYSICS AND METAPHYSICS 99 

to the perfection of transmission : if A/ is the duration of a tone of 
frequency v, there is a relative limit of recognisability given in 
order of magnitude by A/ . Av < ' i. An excellent account of these 
problems has been given by Dr. GABOR in this country, and in 
America a book with the title "Cybernetics", i.e., the science of 
governing namely by sending out signals and orders has been 
published by NORBERT WIENER, which, though full of rather abstruse 
mathematics, has made quite a sensational stir. In fact the mathe- 
matical analysis of these relations, which has its roots, almost one 
and a half centuries ago, in an investigation by FOURIER on the 
conduction of heat, is rather simple. The main point is that the ideal, 
or pure, or harmonic vibration to which alone a sharp frequency can 
be ascribed, appears in a time-amplitude diagram as an endless 
train of sinoidal waves. Every other curve, for instance a wave 
restricted to a finite interval of time, is a superposition of harmonic 
waves and has a whole Spectrum' of v-values. The same holds for 
real waves expanding hi space where apart from the periodicity in 
time one has a periodicity in space measured by the wave number 
/c; between the length AZ of a train of waves and the width A/c 
of the /c-spectrum one has the relation 

A/ . A/c~ i. 

There is no other logical way of dealing with periodic processes 
or waves than this Fourier analysis, and practical applications have 
amply confirmed the theory. 

Let us return to quantum physics. The 'irrationality' can now be 
formulated more precisely; in order to define v and K sharply, one 
has to have very small Av and A/c, hence a very long duration 
A^i/Av and spatial extension A/<-^i/A/c. So far nothing is 
different from the case of telecommunication, and nothing para- 
doxical. But if one uses the relations E = hv 9 p = fiK and re-writes 
the limiting relations in the form 

A* . AE ~ h, AZ . Aj& ~ h, 

they indicate a paradoxical situation: that with a tiny particle of 
sharp energy and momentum (i.e. small AJ? and Ap) there are 
associated long intervals of time and space A* and A/. What can the 
meaning of A and AZ be? 

The only possible answer is, that they mean the limits for deter- 
mining the position of the particle in time and space. They are 
indeed nothing but HEISENBERG'S much discussed uncertainty 
relations. 



IOO PHYSICS AND METAPHYSICS 

Thus it is seen that the very first quantum laws lead necessarily 
to a mutual restriction in the accuracy attainable in space-time 
location on the one hand, energy-momentum determination on the 
other. As BOHR has stressed again and again, we are confronted here 
with a logical alternative : either to deny the validity of an enormous 
amount of experience confirming the quantum laws E hv, 
p = fiK, or to accept the existence of those limits for the determina- 
tion of such pairs of quantities, as time-energy, co-ordinate-momen- 
tum, which in the mechanical terminology are called conjugate. 
The most remarkable thing is that in spite of the completely new 
and revolutionary basic situation it was possible to develop a quan- 
tum mechanics which is a straightforward generalization of classical 
mechanics, extremely similar in mathematical form and consider- 
ably more perfect in its structure. It is true that the simple way of 
describing variable quantities as functions of time has to be given 
up and a more abstract method introduced where physical quan- 
tities are represented by non-commuting symbols (i.e. symbols 
with which one can form sums and products; the value of the latter 
however depends on the order of the factors). 

I shall never forget the thrill which I experienced when I suc- 
ceeded in condensing HEISENBERG'S ideas on quantum conditions 
in the mysterious equation pq qp = A/2m, which is the centre 
of the new mechanics and was later found to imply the uncertainty 
relations. 

The transition from the symbols to actual quantities which can 
be measured is made by the introduction of a quantity called wave 
function, which describes the state in which a system is found as far 
as it can be described : its square is the probability density for finding 
the given data (e.g. co-ordinates of particles) in a given small 
region, analogous to the distribution function of ordinary statistics. 
There is, however, a fundamental difference. 

Suppose two beams of particles coming from the same source 
counted separately, give the results fa* and fa 2 ; if by a suitable 
arrangement they can be made to overlap and be counted together, 
the result is (fa + fa) 2 , which differs from the sum fa* + fa* 
(by 2 fa fa). One has 'interference' of probabilities, as is well known 
from the case of light quanta or photons, the particles whose 
abundance is measured by the square of the intensity of an electro- 
magnetic wave. But I cannot enter into a technical description of 
wave mechanics which has been developed from the foundations 
laid by DE BROGLIE, through the ingenuity of SCHRODINGER, DIRAG, 
and others. It suffices to say that a wave function ft can be regarded 
as a packet of harmonic waves of different v and /c, and that the 



PHYSICS AND METAPHYSICS id I 

physical quantities like co-ordinates, momenta, energies q, p, E, 
are operators distorting the ^-function, and thus determining the 
strengths of the harmonic components of the packet from which, 
by squaring, the probability of the appearance of particles with 
given E = hv, p = HK is obtained. 

Thus the new mechanics is essentially statistical and, in regard to 
the distribution of particles, completely ^deterministic. Yet it 
preserves, strangely enough, some similarity to classical mechanics, 
as the law of propagation of the function i/r, the so-called SCHROD- 
INGER equation, is of the same type as the wave equations of elasticity 
or electro-magnetism. One has therefore the somewhat paradoxical 
situation, that there is no determinism for physical objects, like 
small particles, but for the probability of their appearance. Yet 
this determination of the ^-function needs extremely much more 
data than we are accustomed to in classical mechanics (initial 
positions and velocities of particles). In fact it needs a knowledge, 
or at least a hypothetical knowledge, of ^ everywhere at given time 
and at the boundaries at all times, for the region and period in 
question; or in other words: predictions even of probabilities alone 
can be made only with reference to the whole situation, to the 
apparatus used. One must decide beforehand which feature one 
wishes to investigate, and one must construct the instrument corres- 
pondingly. Then the effect can be predicted, in terms of particles, 
as a probability of their appearance under the conditions of the 
experiment (e.g. with given momentum), either at a certain finite 
region independent of time, or at a later time. That is in complete 
harmony with the meaning of causality which I have suggested. 
The use of this terminology is not a mere decoration; for it is 
essential to be clear that here the metaphysical, irreducible concept 
of necessity in the relation of two sets of things is postulated, which 
is the characteristic feature of the scientific attitude to the world. 

Summarizing, we may say that while classical physics assumes 
natural phenomena going on, independent of the incidence of obser- 
vation and describable without reference to observation, quantum 
physics claims only to describe and predict a phenomenon in 
relation to a well defined mode of observation or instrumental 
arrangement. But one can, of course, use different instruments for 
observing the same class of phenomena; the propagation of light for 
instance can be investigated by prisms or gratings with help of 
photographic plates or Geiger counters. If every arrangement, from 
the standpoint of quantum mechanics, has to be considered separ- 
ately, what is the common feature of all of them? For instance, if 
by one arrangement we can determine the spatial distribution of 



102 PHYSICS ANB METAPHYSICS 

electrons, by others their distribution in energy, how can we know 
if and when we have exhausted all possibilities? 

This question has been discussed in detail by NIELS BOHR under 
the title Complementarity. It is true that he presents his ideas in a 
little different way: he is keenly intent to show by simple examples 
how one can intuitively understand the wholeness of an experi- 
mental situation and the mutual exclusiveness and complementarity 
of two such situations by using nothing but the uncertainty principle 
in its simplest form. I think that his motive in spending much 
ingenuity and effort on this task is the tragic situation that the 
philosophical attitude accepted by him and presented here by 
myself, also accepted by the whole international community of 
atomic physicists, has not found favour in the eyes of just those men 
who have contributed most to the development of quantum theory, 
PLANCK and EINSTEIN. PLANCK preserved always a cautious attitude 
to the revolutionary consequence of his own discovery, but Einstein 
went further and made repeated efforts to show by simple examples 
that the renunciation of determinism and the uncertainty relation 
are wrong. Just these examples have been studied by BOHR, in 
collaboration with Professor ROSENFELD, who is now here in Man- 
chester; in every case EINSTEIN'S objections could be refuted by a 
refined study of the experimental situation. The main point is that 
an instrument, by its very definition, is a physical system whose 
structure can be described in ordinary language and whose function- 
ing in terms of classical mechanics. Indeed, this is the only way in 
which we can communicate about it with one another. For instance 
any spatial location needs a rigid frame, any measurement of time a 
mechanical clockwork, while on the other hand a determination of 
momentum and energy needs a break of rigidity and mechanical 
connection, a freely movable part of the instrument to which the laws 
of conservation can be applied. Now BOHR shows that these two 
types of arrangement are mutually exclusive and .complementary, 
in exact agreement with the results of the theory. If you use a 
diaphragm with a slit for fixing a co-ordinate of a particle passing 
through it, the diaphragm must be fixed to the frame of the instru- 
ment; if you wish to know whether a particle has really passed .the 
slit, the diaphragm must be movable so as to be able to recoil. You 
cannot have it both ways. By taking this complementarity into 
account, one can describe experiments without contradictions. 
Sometimes this is not quite easy. I cannot refrain from indicating 
one example, which EINSTEIN brought forward at the Solvay, Con- 
ference in 1930, with the purpose of showing that it was possible .to 
determine the exact time of an atomic -event and the change- of 



PHYSICS AND METAPHYSICS 103 

energy simultaneously, namely by making use of the relation 
E = me 2 , derived from the theory of relativity. One has only to 
determine the mass m by weighing, to find the energy E. Assume 
radiation enclosed in a box with a shutter which is worked by a 
clockwork inside the box and allows the escape of a given amount of 
energy, one or several photons, at a moment fixed with any accuracy 
desired. Moreover, you could weigh the whole box before and after 
this event and thus measure the energy released with any accuracy 
wanted, in contradiction to the reciprocal indeterminacy of time 
and energy assumed by quantum mechanics. This seems to be a 
serious challenge. BOHR'S answer is that the emission of energy is 
equivalent to a change of weight and therefore a displacement of 
the balance which must be compensated. But this displacement in 
the gravitational field of the earth is coupled with a change of rate 
of the clock. All these effects can be determined within limits of 
accuracy which depend on one another and produce the result, 
that EINSTEIN'S method does not work. 

I shall now describe this in more detail. As the uncertainty AT 
of a measurement of time is proportional to the time measured, we 
must avoid delay and hang our box directly on the balance. If the 
shutter is opened the balance will move and can then be readjusted 
with an accuracy A#. As this happens in the field of the earth g, 
there is a change of gravitational potential O = gq, at the place of 
the clock, which is fixed with a latitude AO = g&q. The reading 
of the clock in the time interval T necessary for this according to 
the general theory of relativity, will have a relative uncertainty 



T c* c* ' 

If in this time Tthe weight of the box is determined with an accuracy 
Am, one has, from NEWTON'S law of motion, for the latitude in 
measuring the momentum of the box, Ap = g Am T. By sub- 
stituting the values of A# and Ap from these relations in A/> . Ag 

rw h, one finds 

t& \T 
A~A/>. A = Amr-^ = c 2 AmAr= AE. AT, 

according to the relativistic connection between mass and energy. 
Hence it is impossible to determine energy and time of release as 
well, with arbitrary accuracy. 

You will find numerous examples in BOHR'S GifFord Lectures. 
While I wrote this, a new book came into my hands, Albert Einstein, 
Philosopher and Scientist (The Library of Living Philosophers: Editor, 
Paul Arthur Schilpp, 1949), which contains articles of many philo- 



104 PHYSICS AND METAPHYSICS 

sophers and theoretical physicists on different aspects of EINSTEIN'S 
work, amongst them also one by NIELS BOHR and one by myself. 
The most interesting part of the work is a scientific autobiography 
by EINSTEIN, and a summarizing article in which he answers the 
criticism in the previous essays. This is most fascinating reading, 
but with all respect to the great physicist, I cannot accept his 
arguments against the philosophy of the quantum physicists. All 
essential points are treated in BOHR'S article where he gives a 
delightful account of a number of discussions he had with EINSTEIN. 
But the latter persists in his opposition, and declares himself firmly 
convinced that the present theory, though logically consistent, is an 
incomplete description of physical systems. His main arguments 
are not so much derived from considerations of causality, but from 
the new attitude to the meaning of physical reality which it implies. 
Let me quote his words (p. 672) : Tor me ... the expectation that 
the adequate formulation of the universal laws involves the use of all 
conceptual elements which are necessary for a complete description, 
is more natural*, namely than the ideas of the quantum physicists, 
and he insists that the emission of, say, an a-particle by a radioactive 
atom with definite energy must happen at a definite time predictable 
from theory otherwise he calls the description conceptionally 
incomplete. Yet he, himself, has taught us in the case of relativity 
that this argument is wrong. There you have an infinite number of 
equivalent inertial systems, each of which can be assumed to be at 
rest with the same right. But there is no way of deciding experi- 
mentally which is truly or absolutely at rest. EINSTEIN'S opponents 
pointed out that they regarded a description of the world as con- 
ceptionally incomplete which denied the existence of a system 
absolutely at rest, even if there is no experimental way of finding it. 
This antirelativistic argument is just as strong as EINSTEIN'S anti- 
quantistic one, as everybody has experienced who was asked to 
conceive a light wave without a material ether as a carrier of the 
vibrations. 

The generation to which EINSTEIN, BOHR and I belong, was 
taught that there exists an objective physical world, which unfolds 
itself according to immutable laws independent of us; we are watch- 
ing this process as the audience watches a play in a theatre. 
EINSTEIN still believes that this should be the relation between the 
scientific observer and his subject. Quantum mechanics, however, 
interprets the experience gained in atomic physics in a different 
way. We may compare the observer of a physical phenomenon 
not with the audience of a theatrical performance, but with that of 
a football game where the act of watching, accompanied by 



PHYSIOS AND METAPHYSICS 1(>5 

applauding or hissing, has a marked influence on the speed and 
concentration of the players, and thus on what is watched. In fact, 
a better simile is life itself, where audience and actors are the same 
persons. It is the action of the experimentalist who designs the 
apparatus, which determines essential features of the observations. 
Hence there is no objectively existing situation, as was supposed to 
exist in classical physics. Not only EINSTEIN, but also others who 
are opposed to our interpretation of quantum mechanics, have said 
that under these circumstances there is no objectively existing 
external world, no sharp distinction between subject and object. 
There is of course some truth in it, but I do not consider this for- 
mulation to be very fortunate. For what do we mean by speaking of 
an objectively existing world? This is certainly a pre-scientific 
notion, never questioned by ordinary man. If he sees a dog, he sees 
a dog whether it sits beside him, jumps about or runs away and 
disappears in the distance as a tiny spot. All these innumerable and 
vastly different sense impressions are united by an unconscious 
process in his mind to the one conception dog, which remains the 
same dog under all these aspects. I propose to express this by saying 
that the mind constructs, by an unconscious process, invariants of 
perception, and that these are what ordinary man calls real things. 
And I think that science does exactly the same, only on a different 
level of perception, namely using all the magnifying devices which 
are the essence of observing and measuring. 

The innumerable possible observations are linked again by some 
permanent features, invariants, which differ from those of ordinary 
perception, but are nevertheless in the same way indicators of 
things, objects, particles. For in describing what we observe even 
with the most refined instrument we have no other language than 
the ordinary one. Thus atomistic objects have, it is true, not all the 
properties of ordinary objects, but they have enough definite pro- 
perties to ascribe to them physical reality of the same kind as to a 
dog. I think the fact that various observations of electrons give 
always the same charge, rest-mass and spin, justifies perfectly 
speaking of them as real particles. 

Here is another point where I disagree with EINSTEIN'S philosophy. 
He accepts the doctrine of conventionalism which in my youth was 
powerfully advocated by the great French mathematician HENRI 
PoiNCARi. According to this view all human concepts are free 
inventions of the mind and conventions between different minds, 
justifiable only by their usefulness in ordinary experience. This may 
be right in a restricted sense, namely for the abstract parts of 
theories, but not for the connection of the theories with observations, 



IO6 PHVSICS AND METAPHYSICS 

with real things. It neglects the psychological fact that the building 
of language is not a conscious process. And even in the abstract part 
of science the use of concepts is often decided by facts, not by 
conventions. 

An instructive example is SCHRODINGER'S attempt to interpret 
his electronic waves as a diffuse cloud of electricity, sacrificing the 
particle concept. It was soon abandoned, since electrons could be 
counted. The corpuscular character of the electron is certainly not 
a convention. 

If we thus have to attribute a definite reality to the particles, 
what about the waves ? Are they also real and in what sense? It has 
been said that electrons appear sometimes as waves, sometimes as 
particles, perhaps changing over every Sunday and Wednesday, 
as a great experimentalist mockingly remarked, obviously in a fit of 
anger about the somersaults of the theorists. I cannot agree to this 
view. In order to describe a physical situation, one has to use both 
waves, describing a 'state', i.e. the whole experimental situation, 
and particles, the proper objects of atomic research. Though the 
wave functions are representing, by their square, probabilities, they 
have a character of reality. That probability has some kind of reality 
cannot be denied. How could, otherwise, a prediction based on 
probability calculus have any application to the real world? I am 
not deeply interested in the numerous attempts to make this more 
understandable. It seems to me, just as the necessity of the causal 
relations of classical physics, something beyond physics, a meta- 
physical idea. The same holds for the wave functions of quantum 
mechanics. One could call the use of particles and waves in physics 
a duality in the description, which should be strictly distinguished 
from complementarity. 

Let us now finally ask whether these new developments in physics 
have any bearing on other subjects, and principally on the great 
problems of metaphysics. There is first the eternal dispute between 
idealism and realism in philosophy. I do not think that the new 
ways in physics can produce any weighty argument for one side or 
the other. Whoever believes that the only important reality is the 
realm of ideas, of the spirit, should not occupy himself with science. 
The scientist must be a realist, he must accept his sense impressions 
as more than hallucinations, as messages of a real outer world. In 
disentangling these messages he uses ideas of a very abstract kind, 
group theory in spaces of many or even infinitely many dimensions 
and things like that, but finally he has his observational invariants 
representing real things with which he learns to operate like any 
craftsman with his wood or metaL Modern theory has made the part 



PHYSICS AND METAPHYSICS IO7 

of the ideas more extended and refined, but not changed the 
whole situation. 

But a real enrichment of our thinking is the idea of comple- 
mentarity. The fact that in an exact science like physics there are 
mutually exclusive and complementary situations which cannot be 
described by the same concepts, but need two kinds of expressions, 
must have an influence, and I think a welcome influence, on other 
fields of human activity and thought. Here again NIELS BOHR has 
shown the way. In biology the concept of life itself leads to a comple- 
mentary alternative: the physico-chemical analysis of a living 
organism is incompatible with its free functioning and leads in its 
extreme application to death. In philosophy there is a similar 
alternative in the central problem of free will. Any decision can be 
considered on one side as a process in the conscious mind, on the 
other as a product of motives, implanted in the past or present from 
the outside world. If one sees in this an example of complementarity 
the eternal conflict between freedom and necessity appears to be 
based on an epistemological error. But I cannot enter into the 
discussion of these questions which are only just beginning to be 
seen in this way. Let me conclude by a remark on RUSSELL'S defini- 
tion of metaphysics from which I started: that it is an attempt to 
conceive the world as a whole by means of thought. Has the lesson 
in epistemology which we learned from physics any bearing on this 
problem? I think it has, in showing that even in restricted fields a 
description of the whole of a system in one picture is impossible; 
there are complementary images which do not apply simultaneously 
but are nevertheless not contradictory and exhaust the whole only 
together. This is, I think, a very healthy doctrine, which properly 
applied may remove many violent disputes not only in philosophy 
but in all ways of life. For instance, in politics. The president of the 
Russian Academy of Sciences, Professor VAVILOV, has published (in 
Vox) an interesting article in which he explained the ideas of 
dialectical materialism and used as example the development of 
optics. The thesis 'light consists of particles 5 and the antithesis light 
consists of waves 5 fought with one another until they were united 
in the synthesis of quantum mechanics, and the same holds for 
electrons and other constituents of matter. That is very well and 
indisputable. Only why not apply it to the thesis Liberalism (or 
Capitalism), the antithesis Communism, and expect a synthesis, 
instead of a complete and permanent victory for the antithesis? 
There seems to be some inconsistency. But the idea of complement- 
arity goes deeper. In fact this thesis and antithesis represent two 
psychological motives and the corresponding economic forces, both 



loB PHYSICS AND METAPHYSICS 

justified in themselves but, in their extremes, mutually exclusive. 
Complete freedom of the individual in economic behaviour is in- 
compatible with the existence of an orderly state, and the totalitarian 
state is incompatible with the development of the individuum. There 
must exist a relation between the latitudes of freedom A/* and of 
regulation Ar, of the type A/ . Arr^p, which allows a reasonable 
compromise. But what is the 'political constant 9 p ? I must leave this 
to a future quantum theory of human affairs. The world which is 
so ready to learn the means of mass-destruction from physics, would 
do better to accept the message of reconciliation contained in the 
philosophy of complementarity. 



PHYSICS IN THE LAST FIFTY 
YEARS* 

[First published in Nature, Vol. 168, p. 625, 1951.] 



'T'HE following review is based on personal recollections and < 
A claim historical accuracy and completeness. I shall tell yot 



I cannot 

I accuracy and completeness. I shall tell you what 
has impressed me most, since I attended, in 1901, my first lecture at 
the University of Breslau, my home city. We were taught what is 
called to-day classical physics, which was at that time believed to 
be a satisfactory and almost complete description of the inorganic 
world. But even MAXWELL'S theory of the electromagnetic field was, 
about 1900, not a part of the ordinary syllabus of a provincial 
German university, and I remember well the impression of bewilder- 
ment, admiration and hope which we received from the first lecture 
on this subject given to us by the then young and progressive 
lecturer CLEMENS SCHAEFER (still active at Cologne). 

The first great event of a revolutionary character happened in 
1905 with EINSTEIN'S theory of relativity. I was at that time ha 
Gottingen and well acquainted with the difficulties and puzzles 
encountered in the study of electromagnetic and optical phenomena 
in moving bodies, which we thoroughly discussed in a seminar held 
by HILBERT and MTNKOWSKI. We studied the recent papers by 
LORENTZ and POINCARE, we discussed the contraction hypothesis 
brought forward by LORENTZ and FITZGERALD and we knew the 
transformations now known under LORENTZ'S name. MINKOWSKI 
was already working on his four-dimensional representation of space 
and time, published in 1907, which became later the standard 
method in fundamental physics. Yet EINSTEIN'S simple consideration 
by which he disclosed the epistemological root of the problem (the 
impossibility of defining absolute simultaneity of distant events 
because of the finite velocity of light signals) made an enormous 
impression, and I think it right that the principle of relativity is 
connected with his name, though LORENTZ and POINCAR should 
not be forgotten. 

Although relativity can rightly be regarded as the culmination of 
nineteenth-century physics, it is also the mainspring of modern 

* Substance of a paper read on August I3th before Section A (Mathematics 
and Physics) of the British Association meeting at Edinburgh. 

109 



HO PHYSICS IN THE LAST FIFTY YEARS 

physics because it rejected traditional metaphysical axioms, NEW- 
TON'S assumption about the nature of space and time, and affirmed 
the right of the man of science to construct his ideas, including 
philosophical concepts, according to the empirical situation. Thus a 
new era of physical science began by an act of liberation similar to 
that which broke the authority of PLATO and ARISTOTLE in the 
time of the Renaissance. 

That result of relativity which later proved to be the most im- 
portant, namely, the equivalence of mass and energy as expressed 
by the formula E= me*, was at that time considered to be of great 
theoretical, but scarcely of any practical, interest. 

In 1913 EINSTEIN'S first attempt on general relativity became 
known; it was perfected two years later. It is the first step not only 
beyond Newtonian m^ta-physics, but also beyond Newtonian physics. 
It is based on an elementary but so far unexplained fact that all 
bodies fall with the same acceleration. To this day it is this empirical 
foundation which I regard as the corner-stone of the enormous 
mathematical structure erected on it. The logical way which led 
from this fact to the field equations of gravitation seems to me more 
convincing than even the confirmation of the astronomical predic- 
tions of the theory, as the precession of the perihelion of Mercury, 
the deflexion of light by the sun and the gravitational shift of 
spectral lines. 

EINSTEIN'S theory led to a revival of cosmology and cosmogony 
on an unprecedented scale. I am not competent to judge whether 
it was the theory which stimulated the astronomers to build bigger 
and more powerful instruments, or whether the results obtained fc 
with these, like BUBBLE'S discovery of the expanding universe, 
stimulated the theoreticians to still loftier speculations about the 
universe. The result, however, is undoubtedly that our astronomical 
horizon to-day, in 1951, is vastly wider, our ideas about the creation 
vastly grander than they were at the beginning of the period. We 
can estimate the actual age of the world (some thousand millions 
of years), its present size (determined by the receding nebulae 
reaching the velocity of light) and the total number of nebulae, stars 
and atoms, and we have good reasons for assuming that the laws of 
physics are the same throughout this vast expanse. The names of 
FRIEDMAN, LEMAJTRE, EDDINGTON and ROBERTSON must here be 
mentioned. 

But after this boast let me conclude this section on a note of 
modesty. The fundamental problem of connecting gravitation with 
other physical forces, to explain the strange value of the gravitational 
constant, is still unsolved in spite of EDDINGTON'S obstinate. 



PHYSICS IN THE LAST FIFTY YEARS III 

ingenious attempts. The most promising idea seems to me that of 
DIRAC, developed by JORDAN, that the gravitational constant is not 
a constant at all, but a scalar field quantity, which like the other 
ten, the components of the metric tensor, undergoes a secular 
change and has acquired its present value in the course of time 
elapsed since the creation of the universe. 

Before speaking about the most characteristic features of modern 
physics, atomistics and the quantum concept, I have to dwell for a 
short time upon classical physics which, of course, has not suddenly 
ceased to exist, but continues and flourishes to such a degree that I 
should venture to say: by far the greatest part of the time and effort 
of physicists is still devoted to problems of this kind, even of those, 
frequently found in the United States, who believe that nuclear 
research is the only decent pursuit deserving the name of physics. 

In fact, the progress and success since 1900 in ordinary mechanics, 
elasticity, acoustics, hydro- and aero-dynamics, thermodynamics, 
electrodynamics and optics is spectacular enough. You have only to 
remember that in 1900 the internal combustion engine was in its 
infancy, motor-cars often brought in by horses and the aeroplane a 
fantastic dream. It would be impossible to attempt even the crudest 
sketch of these and other technical developments due to physics. Let 
me only mention a few characteristic points. 

The first is the adoption of a more realistic attitude. In the nine- 
teenth century the mechanics of solids and fluids were beautiful 
mathematical theories well suited for providing examination papers. 
To-day, they tackle actual problems of daily life and technology, 
for example, in hydrodynamics, boundary layers, heat transfer, 
forces on moving rigid bodies like the wings of aeroplanes, the 
stability of these, even for supersonic velocities. Among the pioneers 
whom I personally knew are G. I. TAYLOR, PRANDTL, KARMAN. In 
elasticity we have a similar development; the narrow field of 
problems accessible to analytical solutions has been enormously 
extended by numerical methods (SOUTHWELL'S relaxation method) 
and the results are checked by photoelastic observations on trans- 
parent models. 

This trend has been strongly assisted by the invention of mechani- 
cal and electrical computing machines. The speed and power of the 
modern instruments based on electronic valves has stirred the 
imagination of the world and given rise to a new science, cybernetics, 
the advocates of which expect a revolution of human civilization 
from these artificial brains a belief which I do not share. 

Acoustics, the branch of elasticity dealing with the propagation of 
waves, was confronted by numerous problems through the invention 



U2 PHYSICS IN THE LAST FIFTY YEARS 

of the gramophone, the telephone and broadcasting. Here again 
the electronic valve was a powerful tool. Ultrasonic vibrations have 
been used for studying the elastic properties of crystals, for signalling 
and for time-keeping. The clock controlled by the oscillations of a 
piezo-quartz crystal seems to be more accurate and reliable than 
ordinary pendulum clocks. 

Prof. ANDRADE has given an account of the origin and the develop- 
ment of thermodynamics which in 1900 was considered to be com- 
plete, with its two fundamental theorems (conservation of energy, 
increase of entropy). But this complacent conviction was wrong 
here as in many other cases. 

In 1907 NERNST added a third theorem concerning the behaviour 
of substances at zero temperature. Of its numerous applications to 
physics and physical chemistry I can only mention the prediction of 
chemical equilibria and reactions, as exemplified by HABER'S method 
of fixing nitrogen from the air (1914). The experimental approach 
to absolute zero made great strides. KEESOM arrived in 1931 at o*7K 
with the help of liquid helium. GIAUQUE and MACDOUGALL devised 
in 1933 a new method for cooling, using the demagnetization of 
paramagnetic salts. The absolute scale of temperature was extended 
below iK by KURTI and SIMON (1938) and others. Strange 
phenomena were discovered in this region, the supraconductiviry of 
metals by KAMERLINGH-ONNES in 1911, and the superfluidity of 
liquid helium by KEESOM and WOLFKE in 1927, ALLEN and MEISNER, 
KAPITZA and others. 

Even at higher temperatures new phenomena were found, for 
example, in the field of highly concentrated electrolytic solutions 
where the names of BJERRUM, G. N. LEWIS, DEBYE and HUGKEL 
must be mentioned. 

An approach to extreme conditions from another angle was 
made by BRIDGMAN (since 1905), who systematically investigated 
the properties of matter under high pressure, reaching more 
than 100,000 atmospheres. His latest triumph is the observation 
of the breakdown of the electronic shells of alkali atoms under 
pressure. 

Of great importance seem to me the recent investigations started 
by ONSAGER in 1930 and continued by GASIMIR, PRIGOGINE, DE 
BOER and DE GROOT, by which thermodynamics is generalized so as 
to apply to irreversible processes, by combining the classical laws of 
flow with one single result of statistical mechanics, the so-called 
principle of microscopic reversibility. The results seem to have a 
bearing on the understanding of the processes going on in living 



PHYSICS IN THE LAST FIFTY YEARS 1 13 

The progress of electrodynamics is obvious to everybody in 
technical applications : improvements in the production of power 
and its transmission over long distances; telecommunication methods, 
such as telegraphy, telephony and wireless transmission. In 1900 
electromagnetic waves were a laboratory experiment. Since MAR- 
CONI'S success in 1895 broadcasting has become a powerful factor 
in human affairs. 

Electromagnetic waves comprise the whole of optics, but it would 
be quite impossible to give an account of the progress in all branches 
of optical research and practice. The improvements and refinements 
of all kinds of optical apparatus, of the experimental and theoretical 
investigation of diffraction, refraction, absorption and scattering are 
enormous. Let me mention only a few outstanding achievements in 
spectroscopy because of their bearing on atomic physics : the dis- 
covery of the ZEEMAN and STARK effect, the disentanglement of 
spectral series by RYDBERG, PASCHEN, RUNGE, Rrrz and others, the 
RAMAN effect, the extension of the spectrum towards the ultra- 
violet and infra-red, and finally the closing of the gap, still existing 
in 1900, between the longest light or heat waves and the shortest 
radio waves. The pressure of war helped to develop the method 
known as radar. In the laboratory it provided the magnetic reson- 
ance effect, used for the study of atoms, molecules, crystals (GLEETON 
and WILLIAMS, 1934; GRIFFITH, 1948), and even for the determina- 
tion of nuclear spin and quadrupole moments (RABI, 1938). It has 
also enriched our knowledge of the world at large by the application 
to the ionosphere (APPLETON and BARNETT, BREIT and TUVE, 1925) 
and to celestial bodies. Reflexions have been obtained from the 
moon (U.S. Signal Corps, 1948) and from meteors (HEY and 
STEWART, 1946), and waves coming from the Milky Way (JANSKI, 
1931) have been observed. This new radio-astronomy will have a 
profound influence on cosmology. 

We now come to atomistics. Although firmly established in the 
nineteenth century, there were still, in 1900, some distinguished 
physicists who did not believe in atoms. To-day, such people would 
be regarded as 'cranks', since the evidence for the atomistic structure 
of matter is overwhelming. 

There are two different but closely interwoven problems to be 
answered by atomistics: (i) What is the nature of the atoms? (2) 
How can the behaviour of matter in bulk be accounted for in terms 
of the collective action of atoms ? 

Let us begin with the latter question, as it has been answered for 
a special type of matter already in the nineteenth century: I mean 
the kinetic theory of gases and its extension to more general systems 



114 PHYSICS IN THE LAST FIFTY YEARS 

in statistical equilibrium through GIBBS' statistical mechanics. This 
was in 1900 a reasonable hypothesis. But EINSTEIN'S explanation of 
the Brownian movement in 1904 and SMOLUCHOWSKI'S consecutive 
work in 1906 provided direct physical evidence for the correctness 
of the kinetic theory and led PERRIN in 1909 to a reliable value of 
the number of atoms in the gram-molecule. 

The theory of compressed gases and condensation started by VAN 
DER WAALS in 1873 has been much improved and modernized by 
URSELL (1927), MAYER (1937) and others. 

A statistical treatment of paramagnetism was given by LANGEVIN 
in 1905, and extended to ferro-magnetism by WEISS in 1907. This 
was the first example of a type of statistical problem dealing with 
so-called order-disorder phenomena, to which, for example, the 
properties of alloys belong. These methods are to-day of great 
practical importance. 

The logical foundations of statistical mechanics were critically 
examined by PAUL and TATYANA EHRENFEST (1911) and its mathe- 
matical methods vastly developed by DARWIN and FOWLER (1922). 

While a satisfactory kinetic theory of liquids, in spite of great 
efforts, is still lacking even to this day, our knowledge of the solid 
state has been greatly increased. This work is closely connected 
with research on X-rays. The nature of X-rays was controversial 
until 1912. Selective absorption and polarization discovered by 
BARKLA in 1909 indicated wave structure. A year later W. H. BRAGG 
found evidence for corpuscular structure. In 1912 POHL and WALTER 
obtained diffraction at a slit from which Sommerfeld estimated 
the wave-length. The dispute was finally settled in favour of waves 
when LAUE and his collaborators found, in 1912, diffraction of 
X-rays by crystals, demonstrating at the same time the atomistic 
nature of solids, the lattice structure of crystals, which had been 
hypothetically assumed for a long time. 

In the hands of W. H. and W. L. BRAGG this method opened a 
new science, atomistic crystallography, which abounds in ingenious 
experiments and mathematical considerations, as the systematic 
application of group theory initiated by SOHNKE as early as 1879 
and perfected by SCHONFLIES and FEDOROW in 1891. 

Upon this empirical geometry of crystal lattices there has been 
erected a dynamical theory which actually started as one of the first 
applications of quantum theory with EINSTEIN'S work of 1907 on the 
specific heat of solids at low temperatures, and its refinements by 
DEBYE and by KARMAN and myself in 1910, which, however, has 
also a large field of application in the classical domain, predicting 
relations between elastic, thermal and optical properties of crystals. 



PHYSICS IN THE LAST FIFTY YEARS 115 

While for a time the ideal lattice was the central object of study, we 
begin to-day to understand the reasons why actual crystals do in 
many ways deviate from this ideal pattern. 

Many of these investigations are independent of a detailed 
knowledge of the atoms themselves, using only some crude averages 
of their geometrical and dynamical properties, like diameter, charge, 
dipole moment, polarizability, etc. 

The problem that remains is to understand these averages; that 
means, to investigate the nature of the atoms themselves. 

The research in the structure of the atom is intimately connected 
with radioactivity. The discovery of radioactivity belongs to the 
nineteenth century. Its rapid development is mainly due to one 
man Lord RUTHERFORD. He demonstrated the atomistic character 
of the a- and ^-radiation by counting the particles, using first the 
scintillation method of CROOKES (1903), later the Geiger counter 
(1908). In the later development of counting methods a decisive 
factor was the amplifying electronic valve, invented in its simplest 
form (diode) by FLEMING in 1904 and improved (triode, pentode, 
etc.) by DE FOREST in 1907 and LANGMUIR in 1915. 

Let me mention here some other experimental techniques of great 
importance which enable us not only to count but also actually to 
see the tracks of particles: C. T. R. WILSON'S cloud chamber (1911) 
and its refinement by BLAGKETT (1937), the counter-controlled 
cloud chamber. Then the method of photographic tracks discovered 
by BLAU and WURMBACHER in 1937, which through the improve- 
ment of emulsions has become a most efficient tool for studying 
atomic processes. 

The first revolutionary results, obtained with the then available 
primitive experimental technique by RUTHERFORD and SODDY 
about 1900, were the laws of radioactive disintegration which 
shattered the belief in the invariability of the chemical elements. 
These laws differ from the ordinary deterministic laws of classical 
physics, being intrinsically statistic and ^deterministic. 

At the same time ample proof for the existence of isotopes was 
found among the radioactive elements. Later, in 1913, J. J. THOMSON 
discovered the first example of isotopy among ordinary elements 
(neon) by electromagnetic deflexion. From here came on one hand 
ASTON'S mass spectrograph (1919), the renewal of PROUT'S hypo- 
thesis and the modern version of the Periodic Table with its arrange- 
ment of the atoms according to nuclear charge (atomic number ) 
as opposed to mass (mass number A); on the other hand, the 
separation of isotopes in bulk as preformed to-day on an industrial 
scale for the production of fissionable material. 



I j6 PHYSICS IN THE LAST FIFTY YEARS 

The distinction between these two numbers and A is mainly 
due to RUTHERFORD'S second great discovery (1911), the nucleus, 
obtained through the observation of scattering of a-rays. The result 
that COULOMB'S law is valid down to nuclear dimensions suggested 
to RUTHERFORD the planetary model of the atom, with the nucleus 
in place of the sun, and electrons in place of the planets. A welcome 
confirmation of this was soon (1913) provided by MOSELEY with 
the help of X-ray spectra. But formidable theoretical difficulties 
arose because of the lack of stability of such systems according to 
the laws of classical mechanics. 

In fact, atomic research had reached here a point where progress 
was not possible without a radical change of our fundamental 
conceptions. 

This revolution of thought was already in progress. It had started 
in 1900, just at the beginning of this period of review, when PLANCK 
convinced himself that the observed spectrum of black bodies could 
not be accounted for by classical mechanics, and put forward the 
strange assumption that finite quanta of energy s exist which are 
proportional to the frequency v, s = Av. 

The physical world received this suggestion with great scepticism 
as it did not fit at all into the well-established wave theory of light. 
Years passed without much happening. But in 1905 EINSTEIN took 
up PLANCK'S idea and gave it a new turn; he showed that by 
assuming the light to be composed of particles, later called photons, 
a quantitative explanation of the photoelectric effect in metals 
and* of similar phenomena is obtained. Using EINSTEIN'S inter- 
pretation MILIJKAN (1910) derived from measurements of the 
photo-effect a value of A in excellent agreement with PLANCK'S 
original one. 

Further evidence for the existence of quanta was given again by 
EINSTEIN in 1907 through his theory of specific heat, mentioned 
already, which not only removed some very disquieting paradoxes 
of the kinetic theory, but also served as a sound foundation of the 
modern theory of molecules and crystals. 

The final triumph of quantum theory was BOHR'S application to 
RUTHERFORD'S planetary model in 1913. It solved the riddle of 
atomic stability, explained the mysterious spectral series and the 
main features of the periodic system. 

BOHR was, right from the beginning, quite clear that the appear- 
ance of the quantum meant a new kind of natural philosophy, and 
so it has turned out. Yet at the same time BOHR was anxious to 
keep the connexion with classical theory as close as possible, which 
he succeeded in doing with the help of his principle of correspondence. 



PHYSICS IN THE LAST FIFTY YEARS I lj 

There followed a period of about twelve years in which BOHR'S 
ideas were confirmed and developed. Here are a few outstanding 
events : 

FRANCK'S and HERTZ'S experiments to demonstrate the existence 
of stationary states with the help of electronic collisions (1914). The 
disentanglement of the multiplet spectra, including X-rays, by 
numerous authors, theoretically guided by BOHR and SOMMERFELD. 
LANDERS formula for the Zeeman effect (1921) which led finally to 
the suggestion of the spinning electron by UHLENBECK and GOUD- 
SMIT (1925). The confirmation of SOMMERFELD'S 'quantization 
of direction' by STERN and GERLACH (1921). The refinement 
of the theory of the periodic system by BOHR himself, confirmed 
at once by the discovery of one of the missing elements, hafnium, 
by COSTER and HEVESY (1922). Then most important FAULT'S 
exclusion principle (1924), which gave a theoretical foundation 
to striking features of observation. Finally, the Gompton effect 
(1923), which demonstrated the usefulness of EINSTEIN'S conception 
of photons. 

Thus the paradoxical situation had to be faced that both the 
undulatory and the corpuscular theory of light were right in fact, 
PLANCK'S formula s = Av states a relation between these contra- 
dictory hypotheses. 

This challenge to reason came to a climax through DE BROGLIE'S 
famous thesis of 1924 in which this duality wave-corpuscle was, by 
a purely theoretical argument, extended to electrons. The _ first 
confirmation was given by ELSASSER (1927) with the help of experi- 
ments on electron scattering on metals made by DAVISSON and 
GERMER (1927), and soon these authors, and independently G. P. 
THOMSON, the son of the discoverer of the electron as a particle, 
produced diffraction patterns with metal foils which established 
definitely the existence of DE BROGLIE'S waves. 

May I mention here in parenthesis that the idea of the electron 
microscope is considerably older than this theory; it was first 
suggested in 1922 by H. BUSCH on the grounds of considerations 
analogous to geometrical optics. After DE BROGLIE the wave theory 
of optical instruments became applicable and the resolving power 
could be determined. I cannot dwell on details, but I wish to remind 
you that to-day not only bacteria and viruses but even big molecules 
can be made visible and photographed. 

The duality wave-corpuscle made an end of the naive intuitive 
method in physics which consists in transferring concepts familiar 
from everyday life to the submicroscopic domain, and forced us to 
use more abstract methods. 



I j# PHYSICS IN THE LAST FIFTY YEARS 

The first form of this new method was mainly based on spectro- 
scopic evidence which led KRAMERS and HEISENBERG to the convic- 
tion that the proper description of the transition between two 
stationary states cannot be given in terms of the harmonic com- 
ponents of these states separately, but needs a new kind of transition 
quantity, depending on both states. HEISENBERG'S quantum 
mechanics of 1926 is the first formulation of rules to handle these 
transition quantities, and these rules were soon recognized by myself 
as being identical with the matrix calculus of the mathematicians. 
This theory was developed by HEISENBERG, JORDAN and myself, 
and independently, in a most general and perfect manner, by DIRAG. 

Again, independently SGHRODINGER developed in 1926 DE 
BROGLIE'S wave mechanics by establishing a wave equation valid not 
only for free electrons but also for the case of external fields and 
mutual interaction, and showed its complete equivalence with 
matrix mechanics. 

Concerning the physical interpretation, SGHRODINGER thought 
one ought to abandon the particle conception of the electron 
completely and to replace it by the assumption of a vibrating con- 
tinuous cloud. When I suggested that the square of the wave function 
should be interpreted as probability density of particles, and pro- 
duced evidence for it by a wave theory of collisions and other 
arguments, I found not only SCHRODINGER in opposition, but also, 
strangely enough, HEISENBERG. On the other hand, DIRAG developed 
the same idea in a mathematically brilliant way, which was soon 
generally accepted, also by HEISENBERG who produced a most 
important contribution by formulating his uncertainty relations 
(1927). These paved the way for a deeper philosophical analysis of 
the foundations of the new theory, achieved by BOHR'S principle of 
complementarity, which replaces to some degree the classical concept 
of causality. 

In a very short time the new theory was well extablished by its 
successes. I can mention only a few points : PAULI'S matrix representa- 
tion of the spin and DIRAC'S relativistic generalization (1928) which 
led to the prediction of the positron, actually found by ANDERSON 
in 1932. Then came the systematic theory of the electronic structures 
of atoms and molecules and their relations to line and band spectra, 
to magnetism and other phenomena. WIGNER showed in 1927 how 
the general features of atomic structures could be found with the 
help of group theory. HARTREE, FOGK, HYLLERAAS and others 
developed numerical methods. The theory of collisions of atoms 
with electrons and other atoms was started by myself and developed 
by BETHE, MOTT, MASSEY and others, from which finally sprang a 



PHYSICS IN THE LAST FIFTY YEARS I IQ 

general theory of the penetration of particles through matter by BOHR. 

Further, the derivation of the nature of the chemical bond, 
initiated by HEITLER and LONDON in 1927, was worked out by 
HUND, SLATER, MULLIKEN, PAULING and others. Even the compli- 
cated phenomena of reaction velocities, including catalytic accelera- 
tion, have been reduced to quantum mechanics. 

Finally came DIRAC'S most important theory of emission, absorp- 
tion and scattering of electromagnetic radiation which led to the 
first systematic attempt of formulating quantum electrodynamics by 
FERMI, JORDAN, HEISENBERG and PAUU (1929), and later to the 
general theory of quantized fields and their interaction ( WENTZEL, 

ROSENFELD, from 1931). 

The last period of our fifty years is dominated by nuclear physics. 
Although the importance of nuclear research is probably greater 
than that of any other branch of physics, I shall be rather short 
about it for it is the most recent phase of our science and scarcely 
yet history. 

The first breaking up of a nucleus was achieved by RUTHERFORD 
in 1919, by bombarding nitrogen with a-rays. Artificially accelerated 
particles were first used by COCKCROFT and WALTON in 1930. At 
that time the nucleus was believed to be composed of protons and 
electrons. But this led to difficulties if one tried to derive the angular 
momenta of nuclei from the spins of the component particles. In 1932 
GHADWICK discovered the neutron, and those difficulties disappeared 
if the nucleus was assumed to consist of protons and neutrons, or 
charged and uncharged 'nucleons'. FERMI showed in 1932 that 
neutrons are most efficient in disrupting nuclei as they are not 
repelled by the nuclear charge. Many of the residual nuclei were 
found by IRENE and FREDERIC JOLIOT-GURIE in 1934 to be radio- 
active themselves. 

The continuous yff-ray spectrum offered great difficulties to the 
understanding until PAUU, in 1931, suggested the existence of the 
neutrino and FERMI developed, in 1934, the neutrino theory of the 
/?-decay where the laws of conservation of energy and momentum 
are preserved. The line spectrum of /?-rays was recognized to be of 
secondary origin, namely, due to the expulsion of electrons from the 
electronic cloud by y-rays emitted by the nucleus. 

The need for fast projectiles was first supplied by the use of cosmic 
rays. These had been discovered by HESS already in 1912 and their 
study has grown to-day into a vast science, covering not only 
nuclear physics but also geophysics, astronomy and cosmology. 

The artificial production of fast particles has made enormous strides 
through the construction of powerful accelerating machines, as that 



120 PHYSICS IN THE LAST FIFTY YEAfeS 

of VAN DE GRAAFF (1931), LAWRENCE'S cyclotron (1931), KERST'S 
betatron (1940) and combinations of these, like the synchrotron. 

The clue to the interpretation of nuclear transformations is 
EINSTEIN'S formula E = me*, or more precisely, the relativistic 
conservation laws of energy and momentum. I am not an expert in 
the new awe-inspiring science of nuclear chemistry and shall make 
no attempt to describe it. I can say only a few words on the theoreti- 
cal problems of nuclear physics. It is remarkable how many 
important facts can be understood by extremely simple models, as, 
for example, GAMOW'S crater model (1928)3 which explains the 
a-decay and the GEIGER-NUTTAL relation between cc-energy and life- 
time; and the liquid-drop model, suggested by VON WEIZSAGKER in 
r 9 2 5> to explain the mass defect (nuclear energy) curve and later 
used successfully by BOHR (1935) to explain the mechanism of 
capture, re-emission and fission. A great amount of work has been 
done on exact quantum-mechanical calculations of the structure and 
properties of light nuclei (in particular the deuteron) and of the 
effect of collisions, with the aim of learning something about the 
nuclear forces. Important results have been, obtained, but altogether 
the situation is not satisfactory. 

Quite independently of detailed theories, the empirical values of 
the nuclear masses (internal energies) indicate that the light nuclei 
have the tendency to fuse, the heavy ones to disintegrate; hence all 
matter, except the elements in the middle of the periodic system 
(iron), is in principle unstable. But reaction velocities are, under 
terrestrial conditions, so extremely slow that nothing happens. It is, 
however, different in the interior of stars; BETHE showed in 1938 
that one can account for the heat developed in the sun and the stars 
by a nuclear catalytic chain reaction, the fusion of four nucleons to 
form a helium nucleus. 

The opposite phenomenon, the fission of the heavy nucleus of 
uranium into almost equal parts, discovered by HAHN and STRASS- 
MANN in 1938, has initiated a new era in the sociological situation of 
our science and very likely in the history of mankind. Here is a list 
of events: 

The establishment in 1939 of the possibility of a self-supporting 
chain reaction by different authors (JouoT, HALBAN and KOVARSKI; 
FERMI; SZILLARD) ; the construction of the first nuclear reactor or 
'pile' under the direction of FERMI in 194.2, and, finally, the harness- 
ing of the industrial power of the United States to produce the 
atom bomb. 

The political and economic implications of this development are 
too formidable to be discussed here; but I cannot refrain from saying 



PHYSICS IN THE LAST FIFTY YEARS 121 

that I, personally, am glad not to have been involved in the pursuit 
of research which has already been used for the most terrible mass 
destruction in history and threatens humanity with even worse 
disaster. I think that the applications of nuclear physics to peaceful 
ends are a poor compensation for these perils. 

However, the human mind is adaptable to almost any situation, 
So let us forget for a while the real issues and enjoy the useful results 
obtained from the pile. In physics the remaining few gaps of the 
Periodic Table have been filled and five or six transuranium elements 
(among them fissionable nuclei like neptunium and plutonium) 
discovered. Innumerable new isotopes of known elements have been 
produced. Some of these can be used as 'tracers' in chemical and 
biological research as first suggested by VON HEVESY in 1913; others 
as substitute for the expensive radium in industrial research and in 
the treatment of cancer. 

From the point of view of natural philosophy the most important 
achievement of the past decade seems to me the discovery of the 
meson, theoretically predicted by YUKAWA in 1935, which showed 
how far we are still removed from a knowledge of the real funda- 
mental laws of physics. YUKAWA became convinced that the forces 
between nucleons are at least as important as the electromagnetic 
forces, and by applying the field concepts in analogy to MAXWELL'S 
theory was able to predict a new particle which has the same rela- 
tion to the nuclear field as the photon to the electromagnetic field, 
but has a finite rest-mass, which from the range of nuclear forces 
could be estimated to be about 300 electron masses. Soon the 
existence of mesons was experimentally confirmed in cosmic rays 
by ANDERSON and NEDDERMEYER in 1936 and later with particles 
produced by the cyclotron in California in 1948. The method of 
photographic tracks has, in the hands of POWELL (from 1940) and 
others, produced a wealth of new results, for example, the sponta- 
neous disintegration of the meson of about 300 electron masses 
into a lighter one of about 200 electron masses and a neutral particle. 
A meson of about 900 electron masses has been fairly well established, 
and it is not unlikely that still more types exist. 

It is obvious that to understand all this a much deeper research 
in the theory of quantized fields and their interaction is necessary. 
A revised and modernized quantum electrodynamics was published 
independently by SCHWINGER in the United States and TOMONAGA 
in Japan in 1947, and from this has sprung a considerable amount 
of literature, aiming at the elimination of divergence difficulties and 
calculating effects of higher order, inaccessible to the older theory. 
A great success was the, explanation of an observation made by 



!22 PHYSICS IN THE LAST FIFTY YEARS 

LAMB and RETHERFORD in 1947, which showed that DIRAC'S 
celebrated theory of the hydrogen spectrum is not quite correct. But 
it becomes more and more clear that all these mathematical refine- 
ments do not suffice, and that a far more general theory has to be 
found s in which a new constant (an absolute length or time, or 
mass) appears and which ought to account for the masses found in 
Nature. I wish to end this outlook into the future with a remark 
I have recently heard from HEISENBERG. We have accustomed 
ourselves to abandon deterministic causality for atomic events ; but we 
have still retained the belief that probability spreads in space (multi- 
dimensional) and time according to deterministic laws in the form 
of differential equations. Even this has to be given up in the high- 
energy region. For it is obvious that the absolute time interval 
restricts the possibility of distinguishing the time order of events. If 
this interval is defined in the rest system it becomes large in a fast- 
moving system according to the relativistic time expansion (in 
contrast to the contraction of length). Hence the indeterminacy of 
time order and therefore of cause-effect relation becomes large for 
fast particles. 

Thus experience again leads us to an alteration of the meta- 
physical foundations of a rather unexpected kind. In fact, traditional 
philosophy has provided the leaders of our science, like EINSTEIN, 
BOHR and HEISENBERG, with problems in so far as it failed to supply 
answers agreeing with experience. I am convinced that although 
physics free from metaphysical hypotheses is impossible, these 
assumptions have to be distilled out of physics itself and continuously 
adapted to the actual empirical situation. On the other hand, the 
continuity of our science has not been affected by all these turbulent 
happenings, as the older theories have always been included as 
limiting cases in the new ones. The scientific attitude and the methods 
of experimental and theoretical research have been the same all 
through the centuries since GALILEO and will remain so. 



THE CONCEPTUAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 

AND THE PROSPECTS OF ITS FUTURE 

DEVELOPMENT 

[37th Guthrie Lecture, delivered March I3th, 1953. First published in Proc. 
Pkys. Soc., A, Vol. LXVI, pp. 501-513, 1953.] 

T ET me begin with a personal remark. Fifty years ago I was a 
-*- J young student of science, in my second academic year. At that 
time PLANCK'S radiation formula and the quantum hypothesis 
were already more than two years old. But I was ignorant of those 
momentous events. We were taught NEWTON'S mechanics and its 
applications, and we were cautiously introduced to MAXWELL'S 
theory of the electromagnetic field. 

To-day the situation may be similar. A great discovery may be 
made somewhere by somebody of which I have heard nothing or 
whose importance I do not see. With increasing age it becomes more 
and more difficult to keep step with contemporary research. My 
knowledge of what is going on in the laboratories and studios all 
over the world is now almost as scanty as it was half a century ago. 
Yet the years have not passed without trace. They have left an 
accumulation of experience over a wide horizon, and this encourages 
me to speak to you about my impressions of the present situation in 
theoretical physics and the direction in which it is moving. A fore- 
cast about the future may appear presumptuous, for science has 
always been full of surprises, unexpected experimental results 
which changed the structure of the theory. Yet I venture certain 
guesses because of a phenomenon which might be called the 'stability 
of the principles 9 . 1 do not suggest that, apart from mathematics, there 
are any principles which are unchangeable, a priori in the strictest 
sense. But I think that there are general attitudes of the mind which 
change very slowly and constitute definite philosophical periods 
with characteristic ideas in all branches of human activities, science 
included. PAULI, in a recent letter to me, has used the expression 
'styles', styles of thinking, styles not only in art, but also in science. 
Adopting this term, I maintain that physical theory has its styles 
and that its principles derive from this fact a kind of stability. They 
are, so to speak, relatively a priori with respect to that period. If you 
are aware of the style of your own time you can make some cautious 

123 



124 THE CONCEPTUAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 

predictions. You can at least reject ideas which are foreign to the 
style of your time. 

I shall not attempt a historical review of physics from this stand- 
point, nor an investigation of the question whether the style of 
science, in particular of physics, depends on other conditions, for 
instance economic ones. I shall just begin with the modern era, 
with GALILEO and NEWTON, and stress solely one characteristic 
point, namely, the separation of subject and object in the descrip- 
tion of natural phenomena. For the Greek philosophers the cause of 
motion, the force producing the motion, was inseparable from a 
living being, man or god, who felt the exertion. Moreover, they used 
ideas of value as a principle of explanation. The planets moved in 
circular (or epicyclic) orbits because the circle is the most perfect 
curve. Perfection reigned in the celestial spheres, corruption on the 
terrestrial level; law and order among the stars, chaos and strife on 
earth. The Christian era introduced new ideas and is certainly a 
separate period with its own style, but in regard to science it relied 
on the ancients and preserved the anthropocentric, subjective 
attitude. The idea of perfection was now personified in God. Natural 
phenomena happen to glorify Him, to punish the wicked, to reward 
the good. This motive is still strong in KEPLER. 

The break came with GALILEO and NEWTON. They introduced 
the disinterested, objective description and explanation which is 
characteristic for the modern epoch. But the ancient style did not 
disappear at once. Traces survived a long time, for instance in the 
metaphysical interpretation of the minimum principles of mechanics. 
MAUPERTUIS certainly believed that the minimum of action was the 
expression of a purpose of Nature or the Creator. Even EULER'S 
writing, where the first rigorous formulation of the principle of least 
action is given, is not free from this metaphysical attitude. It finally 
disappears in LAGRANGE'S work. 

From now on the world is a mechanism, ruled by strict determin- 
istic laws. Given the initial state, all further development can be 
predicted from the differential equations of mechanics. The mini- 
mum principles are not due to nature's parsimony but to human 
economy of thinking, as MAGH said; the integral of action condenses 
a set of differential equations into one simple expression. 

The supposition is that the external world, the object of natural 
science, and we, the observing, measuring, calculating subjects, are 
perfectly separated, that there is a way of obtaining information 
without interfering with the phenomena. 

This is the philosophy of science in which we, of the older genera- 
tion, have grown up. It can be called the Newtonian style, as it is 



THE CONCEPTUAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 125 

modelled on NEWTON'S celestial mechanics. It was extremely success- 
ful also in terrestrial matters, even when it was extended from 
mechanics of material systems to electrodynamic phenomena in vacuo 
and in matter. MAXWELL'S theory takes the polarity between subject 
and object for granted and is strictly deterministic. 

A new era, a new style, commenced in 1900, when PLANCK pub- 
lished his radiation formula and the idea of the quantum of energy. 
Its way was prepared by a long development which revealed the 
inadequacy of classical mechanics to deal with the behaviour of 
matter. The differential equations of mechanics do not determine a 
definite motion, but need the fixation of initial conditions. For 
instance, they explain the elliptic orbits of the planets, but not why 
just the actual orbits exist. But there are regularities concerning 
the latter: BODE'S well known rule. This is regarded as a question of 
the prehistory of the system, a problem of cosmogony, and still 
highly controversial. In the realm of atomistics the incompleteness 
of the differential equations is even more important. The kinetic 
theory of gases was the first example to show that new assumptions 
had to be made about the distribution of the atoms at a fixed instant, 
and these assumptions turned out to be more important than 
the equations of motions; the actual orbits of the particles do not 
matter at all, only the total energy which determines the observable 
averages. Mechanical motions are reversible, therefore the explana- 
tion of the irreversibility of physical and chemical processes needed 
new assumptions of a statistical character. Statistical mechanics 
paved the way for the new quantum era. 

With the quantum came a new attitude to the polarity subject- 
object. It is neither essentially subjective, as the ancient and medi- 
aeval doctrines, nor wholly objective, as the post-Newtonian 
philosophy. 

The change was due to the breakdown of all attempts to under- 
stand atomic phenomena from the standpoint of ordinary mechanics. 
A new atomic mechanics had to be found, and the way leading to 
it proceeded in steps. The most important of these was BOHR'S idea 
of stationary states and transitions between them. The states are 
certain mechanical orbits picked out by simple quantum rules, and 
the energies lost or gained by the transition are connected with 
frequencies of emission and absorption by PLANCK'S quantum law 
E hv. The amazing success of this theory in explaining the 
stability of atoms, the structure of atomic and molecular spectra, 
the periodic system of elements and of many other properties of 
matter did not delude BOHR into believing that this was a final 
solution. He stressed, from the very beginning, the new features of 



126 THE CONCEPTUAL SITUATION IN PUYSICS 

the scheme, namely the indeterministic character of the transitions, 
the appearance of chance in the elementary processes. This means 
the end of the sharp separation of the object observed and the 
subject observing. For chance can be understood only in regard to 
expectations of a subject. 

After twenty-five years of struggle a satisfactory theory was 
obtained, from different sources. One approach, which expresses 
BOHR'S ideas in a logically consistent way, is due to HEISENBERG, 
the so-called matrix mechanics. Another quite independent approach 
was found by DE BROGUE and developed in SCHRODINGER'S wave 
mechanics. In the form given to the theory by DIRAC it is a structure 
of great beauty and perfection, but rather abstract. It has been 
supplemented by a doctrine of measurement, due to HEISENBERG 
and BOHR, which connects the formalism with the experimental 
reality. 

The essential feature is that the physical quantities or, in DIRAG'S 
terminology, 'observables', like coordinate, momentum, energy of a 
particle, components of field strength, etc., are not represented by 
variables, but by symbols with a non-commuting multiplication 
law, or, more concretely, by operators A, which operate on a 
quantity ft, transforming it into another quantity Aft. This function 
ft is a generalization of DE BROGUE'S and SCHRODINGER'S wave 
amplitude and defines the state of the system. It satisfies an equation 
of the deterministic type current in classical theory. Nevertheless it 
does not allow deterministic predictions about the observables, but 
only statistical ones: | ft | 2 is the probability of the state repre- 
sented by ft, and the expectation value of an observable A in this 
state can be expressed in terms of ft. In particular, the accuracy Sq 
of a measurement of a coordinate q (properly defined through the 
expectation value of the mean square deviation) and the accuracy 
Sp for the corresponding momentum p are found to satisfy HEISEN- 
BERG'S uncertainty relation SqSp>h, where h is PLANCK'S constant. 
Similar relations hold for other pairs of 'conjugate' variables. 

In this abstract formulation the words particle, co-ordinate, 
momentum, etc., are used, but obviously with a different meaning 
from ordinary language. A dust particle is supposed to have at a 
given instant a certain position and velocity. An electron or other 
particle obeying the laws of quantum mechanics behaves differently 
for according to the uncertainty rule a definite position (Sq very 
small) demands a large Sp (>hl$q), hence a large uncertainty of 
velocity. This question has been discussed so often that I need not 
dwell upon it. The further development of quantum mechanics has 
revealed more features of strange behaviour, for instance the lack 



TIIE CONCEPTUAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 127 

of individuality of particles, which has very direct and decisive 
consequences for statistical thermodynamics. 

Therefore the question arises how these new conceptions of 
particles and their properties can be handled without coming into 
conflict with the obvious fact that the instruments used in experi- 
menting with them and observing them are ordinary bodies which 
obey Newtonian laws. This is the object of BOHR'S theory of measure- 
ment. The essence of quantum mechanics, stripped of all mathe- 
matical refinement, is the laws of PLANCK and of EINSTEIN-DE 
BROGUE, namely E = hv> p = A/c; here E, p are the energy and 
momentum of a particle, v, K the frequency and wave number of 
the 'corresponding' wave. If one tries to visualize the meaning ^of 
this correspondence in space and time, one finds a paradoxial 
situation. For E, p refer to an extensionless particle, v, K to a har- 
monic wave which by its very definition is infinitely extended in 
time and space. The solution of the paradox must therefore be 
found in an analysis of the use of the concepts of location and 
duration in connection with a train of waves. 

One is accustomed to apply the idea of a definite time interval 
or duration to any ordinary pair of events (e.g. the fall of a stone 
from my hand to the earth). Yet there are seemingly harmless cases 
where this is not justified. The sentence c a musical tone lasts a 
definite time 5 has no rigorous meaning. That is not a purely logical 
statement, but one of fact. Indeed, a sharp staccato on the low pipes 
of an organ sounds badly. For a wave train starting harmonically 
but broken off at a time not large compared with the period of 
vibration is not actually harmonic but a superposition of harmonic 
waves of different frequencies, a wave packet: acoustically ^ a noise. 
This fact is also well known in optics, where it is the basis of the 
theory of the resolving power of instruments, and it has recently 
become most important in the theory of information (obtained by 
transmitting electromagnetic or other waves). 

Elementary considerations on the mutual limitation of St and 
8v, Sx and &c, lead to the relations St 8v > i, $x SK > i. They are 
the root of the uncertainty rules of HEISENBERG; for if they are 
multiplied by h and the PLANCKHDE BROGUE relations used, the 
result is 8t SE> h, dx Sp > h. This consideration in no way mitigates 
the paradoxical, almost irrational, character of the PLANGK-DE 
BROGUE correspondence. But it helps to handle it in such a way 
that contradictions between the results of measurement cannot 

occur. 

Location and duration can be measured only with the help of 
rigid scales and clocks; energy and momentum only with the help 



128 THE CONCEPTUAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 

of mobile parts, which react according to the conservation laws. 
Thus the reciprocal uncertainty can be traced to two types of 
mutually exclusive but complementary experiments. BOHR has 
illustrated this 'complementarity 5 by many instructive examples, 
some of these in response to attacks made by EINSTEIN, who hoped 
to disprove the uncertainty rules by ingenious experimental arrange- 
ments. I think that attempts against the uncertainty laws will cease 
in time. The lasting result of BOHR'S endeavours is the simple 
consideration given above, which shows with irrefutable logic that 
the PLANCK-DE BROGUE laws of necessity imply the duality particles- 
waves and the complementary quality of experimental arrangements 
set up to measure 'conjugate 9 pairs of quantities, like energy-time, 
momentum-location. 

Intimately connected with this duality is the polarity subjective- 
objective. For if an experiment must be set up in a definite way to 
investigate one or the other of a conjugate pair of quantities, it is 
impossible to obtain information of the system considered as such; 
the observer has to decide beforehand which kind of answer he 
wants to obtain. Thus subjective decisions are inseparably mixed 
with objective observations. The same can be seen from the mathe- 
matical description with the help of the state-function ^, which is 
only determined by the whole system, including the means of 
observation which depend on the subject. 

This is a sketch of the modern style of physics which is accepted 
by practically the whole community of experimental and theoretical 
physicists. It fits exactly into the practice of electronics, spectroscopy, 
radioactivity, nuclear physics and also chemistry and astrophysics. 
The questions for which the theory offers answers are just those 
which the experimentalist wants to be answered. He is entirely 
indifferent to orbits of electrons in atoms, of atoms in gases, of 
nucleons in nuclei; he is quite content with stationary states and 
collision cross-sections which the theory supplies. 

I think that this mode of scientific thought is also in conformity 
with the general trend of contemporary philosophy. We have lost 
confidence in the possibility of separating knowledge from decision, 
we are aware of being at every moment spectators and actors in the 
drama of life. BOHR himself has indicated generalizations of his 
'complementary 5 idea to biology and psychology; ancient problems 
like that of the relation of matter and mind, freedom and necessity, 
are thus seen from a new angle. I cannot enter into these deep 
questions, but may mention some fascinating books by VON WEIZ- 
SACKER (1949, 1951), where they are treated with competence and 
good taste. 



THE CONCEPTUAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 129 

I venture the prediction that this style of thinking will last, and 
that a future change, when it comes, will not lead back to the past, 
so-called classical, style but to something more removed from it. My 
confidence in this forecast rests not only on the success of the present 
theory but in my personal affinity for its philosophy. 

However, this view is strongly contested, just by some of those 
who have done most to develop quantum theory. PLANCK himself 
was sceptical. For instance, when he, as President of the Berlin 
Academy, inaugurated SCHRODINGER (who was his successor to his 
chair), he praised him as the man who had re-established determin- 
ism through his wave equation. EINSTEIN, who renewed the cor- 
puscular idea in optics, who introduced the transition probabilities 
between two stationary states and is guilty of other anti-classical 
deviations, has turned with a kind of passion against the statistical 
interpretation of quantum mechanics. I have already mentioned 
his attempts to disprove the uncertainty laws by ingenious contrap- 
tions and BOHR'S refutations of these attacks. When EINSTEIN could 
not maintain the existence of logical flaws in quantum mechanics he 
declared it to be an 'incomplete' description of nature. I have used 
the same expression before in regard to the differential equations of 
classical mechanics which are incomplete without initial values for 
which classical theory gives no law and which, in my opinion, lead 
to absurd consequences. Imagine JV particles fixed in random 
positions and another particle fired amongst them, colliding and 
recoiling, according to classical laws. It is obvious that for large N 
the tiniest deviations of the initial motion produce not small changes 
in the final position, but an enormous variety of large effects. If all 
particles are moving like gas atoms this would hold a fortiori. Thus 
the supposed determinism is an illusion. 

This group of distinguished men, to whom VON LAUE may be 
added, may be called philosophical objectors, or, to use a less 
respectful expression, general grumblers. 

There are those who, aware of the unavoidable consequences of 
the PLANCK-DE BROGUE relations E hv^p hx, want to sacrifice 
these and preserve only one side of the picture. There are the 
particle defenders or />-totallers, and the ^-wave defenders or ft- 
totallers. They are of course all theoretical physicists, and you find 
them well represented in a recently published book* dedicated to 
DE BROGLIE on the occasion of his Goth birthday (1952). DE BROGUE 
himself, though the discoverer of the electron waves, has made 

* This book contains the literature in more complete form than is given here. 
In the list of references at the end of this article papers are mentioned which are 
quoted in the text only by e and others'. 



130 THE CONCEPTUAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 

serious attempts to save determinism by introducing concealed 
parameters. One of his suggestions (DE BROGLIE 1926, 1927) was to 
write a complex ^-function in the form j/r = R exp (zXD) ; then SCHRO- 
DINGER'S wave equation is equivalent to a set of classical equations 
of motion of particles under the action of two forces, one with the 
potential O, the other with a supplementary potential U. The latter 
depends on R and is subject to strong fluctuations due to the inter- 
action of the particles, thus producing the same effect as the un- 
certainty in the current interpretation. A similar suggestion has 
been independently made by MADELUNG (1927). Recently such 
considerations have been renewed and refined by FRENKEL (1950, 
1951) and BLOKHINTZEV (1950, 1951) in Russia, and by BOHM 
(1952) in America. Already in 1932 VON NEUMANN had shown that 
it is impossible to introduce concealed parameters without conflict 
with confirmed results of the current theory. Therefore BOHM is 
anxious to show that in the frame of present knowledge his concealed 
parameters cannot be determined by experiment; he hopes that 
future discoveries will make this possible. But PAULI, in the DE 
BROGLIE volume mentioned, has shown that this attitude leads to 
contradictions; for in problems of statistical thermodynamics the 
concealed parameters must necessarily show their existence and 
produce secular distortions of the BOSE- or the FERMI-DIRAC 
distribution. 

Thus the reactionary ^-totaller movement can be discarded. 

SCHRODINGER has, right from the beginning, taken the opposite 
standpoint: the whole of physics is wave theory, there are no 
particles, no stationary states and no transitions, only waves. I have 
already mentioned that PLANCK welcomed this idea; but the majority 
of physicists continued to use the particle image and to speak of 
atoms, electrons, nuclei, mesons etc. 

Recently SCHRODINGER (1952) has taken up his purification 
campaign and pleaded passionately for ejecting not only particles, 
but also stationary states, transitions, etc., from physics. The motive 
for his discovery of wave mechanics was his violent dislike of BOHR'S 
instantaneous 'quantum jumps', and we can understand his triumph 
when he could represent all these 'absurdities 3 in terms of well-known 
and innocuous resonance phenomena of waves. 

I myself might have a similar motive to declare matrices as the 
only real thing. Allow me to indulge in a personal reminiscence. 
When HEISENBERG published the fundamental paper in which he 
cleared quantum theory from classical remnants and formulated it 
in terms of transition amplitudes, he was my assistant, very brilliant 
but very young, not very learned. In fact he did not exactly know 



THE CONCEPTUAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 131 

what a matrix was, and as he felt stuck he asked for my help. After 
some effort I found the connection with the matrix calculus, and 
I remember my surprise when HEISENBERG'S quantum condition 
turned out to be the matrix equation qp pq = ik. If HEISENBERG 
were here instead of myself he would tell you the same story. The 
matrix form of quantum mechanics was first published by myself 
in collaboration with my pupil JORDAN.* 

However, I have not, and never had, a particular preference for 
the matrix method. When SGHRODINGER'S wave mechanics appeared 
I felt at once that it demanded a non-deterministic interpretation, 
and I guessed that | i/r [ 2 was the probability density; but it took 
some time before I had found physical arguments in favour of this 
suggestion, namely collision phenomena and transitions under 
external forces. Now the strange thing happened that HEISENBERG 
first disagreed and accused me of treason against the spirit of mairix 
mechanics. But he soon came round and produced the wonderful 
reconciliation of particles and waves with the help of his uncertainty 
relation. 

But now I have to return to SGHRODINGER'S attack against 
particles and quantum jumps. It cannot be proved wrong, for the 
^r-function which can be represented as a wave in a multi-dimen- 
sional space contains all physical information provided you know 
how to connect it with experience. And there is the difficulty. We 
have no other language to describe what we do and what we see in 
experimenting than in terms of bodies and their movements. 
SCHRODINGER himself cannot avoid the particle language even when 
he tries to demonstrate the supremacy of the wave language. I have 
dealt with this question in detail at another place (1953) and need 
not repeat it. I think SCHRODINGER'S suggestion is impracticable and 
against the spirit of the time. 

Yet I do not wish to create the impression that I believe the 
present interpretation of quantum theory to be final. I only think 
that a return to Newtonian determinism is impossible. 

I have now arrived at the point where I have to make good my 
promise to try some forecast of the future. 

The fundamental problems of contemporary physics are con- 
cerned with elementary particles and the corresponding fields, in 
particular the explanation of stability or instability, masses, spin 
character, interactions, etc. This is a wide programme which 
includes the whole of nuclear physics and the study of cosmic rays, 

* The early phase of quantum mechanics is misquoted nearly everywhere in the 
literature. I have given a few more examples in my book Natural Philosophy of 
Cause and Chance (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1949), App. 27, p. 188. 



132 THE CONCEPTUAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 

and it leads definitely beyond the scope of current quantum 
mechanics, for the problem of the elementary masses is connected 
with the difficulty of the self-energy of particles. It is well known 
that the self-energy of an electron is infinite even in the classical 
theory of MAXWELL-LORENTZ. In quantum theory this primary 
infinity of the type e z ja (e charge, a radius, limit 0->o) is superposed 
by a variety of other divergent integrals. I have followed these 
investigations only from afar, but my impression is that through the 
work initiated by TOMONAGA (1946) and SCHWINGER (1948) a kind 
of solution has been found: By a profound mathematical method 
called *renormalization ? the actual, intrinsic singularities can be 
separated out and, if infinite, omitted in a way which is uniquely 
fixed by postulating relativistic invariance, and the remaining 
formulae give definite, finite results. DIRAG (1951) wrote about this 
theory: c lt is an ugly and incomplete one, and cannot be considered 
as a satisfying solution of the problem of the electron', and he 
suggests an alternative theory. I think the first part of his judgment 
too hard, for it is a great achievement to have a working formalism 
which in the hands of the initiated leads to the explanation of such 
delicate effects as the LAMB-RETHERFORD shift (1947) in the hydro- 
gen terms and deviations from LANDE'S magnetic factors, etc. But I 
subscribe to the view that this theory is incomplete and circumvents, 
instead of attacking, the actual problem. DIRAG has suggested an 
alternative theory whose main idea is that the occurrence of charge 
in finite quanta, electrons, must be a quantum effect; hence the 
corresponding classical theory should be a pure wave theory. By a 
slight modification of the current formulae he obtains such a wave 
theory, but so far he has not -succeeded in quantizing it. It is possible 
that a satisfying theory of the electromagnetic field and its charges 
can never be obtained because photons and electrons cannot be 
treated without regard to other particles. 

The most conspicuous feature of modern physics is the discovery 
of more and more unstable particles, called mesons. For practical 
purposes linear wave equations for each type of particle are estab- 
lished with non-linear coupling terms between them. It is clear that 
this is a preliminary approach which one day will have to be 
superseded by a coherent theory of matter, in which the different 
masses of the particles appear as eigenvalues of operators or solutions 
of equations. It is now generally accepted that this theory will 
contain an absolute length 0, or an absolute momentum b = hja, 
and that in domains of the dimension a geometry may become 
meaningless. A remarkable attempt to formulate such a situation is 
due to YUKAWA (1949); he regards a field component <j> not as a 



THE CONCEPTUAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 133 

function of the space co-ordinates and time, x, jy, , t, but both <j> 
and #, y, z, t as non-commuting quantities, and postulates certain 
commutation laws between them which are generalizations of 
the current differential equations and go over into them if all 
distances are large compared with the absolute length a. YUKAWA, 
M0LLER (1951), RAYSKI (1951) and others have shown that the 
divergences of the self-energy and other such difficulties can thus be 
avoided. 

The first who clearly saw the necessity of uniting the theories of 
different particles was EDDINGTON. But at this time there were only 
two kinds known, protons and electrons. Thus the discoveries of 
mesons have made his attempt rather obsolete, quite apart from 
the rather fantastic foundations. [His main assumptions led to the 
integral value 137 of the reciprocal fine structure constant i/a 
= hcje 2 , which is almost but not quite in agreement with the latest 
observations, from which the value i/a = 1 37*0364 0*0009 is 
derived (Du MOND and COHEN 1951).] 

I cannot deal with the many attempts to unify the different fields. 
Most of them can be reduced to the following scheme: 

The wave equation (Q + m 2 )^ 1 = o (D is the d'Alembertian 
operator) is replaced by/(C)^ = o, where/(g) = (S i)( 2) 
. . . . ( g n ) is a polynomial of degree n; it describes the motion 
of 72 independent particles with masses m x = y^ . . . . m n Vw 
By using instead of D DIRAG'S operator one can take account of the 
spin.. Theories of this type have been derived by BHABHA (1945) 
and others from considerations of particles with higher spin. I have 
suggested another way to determine the function/() which connects 
this problem with that of the infinities. One can add to /() a 
transcendental factor without zeros. If one has, for instance, the 
differential operator in the domain of one variable q, p 2 m 2 , 
where p = ikSjdq, one can add the factor exp ( |^ 2 ) (where 
b = h\a is taken as unit for p}. This has, in the first place, the 
consequence that the possible momenta are cut off, thus removing 
infinities. And secondly, one can determine the mass m by giving 
the expression (p* m*) exp( J/> 2 ) a proper meaning; it is the 
second Hermitian function of p for m 2 = 2, hence identical with 
its FOURIER transform. This remark suggests the application of the 
general principle that the whole of physics can be formulated in 
terms of transformation groups and their invariants. By postulating 
reciprocal invariance (i.e. against FOURIER transformation) it seems 
to be possible to determine a set of masses as the roots of (Hermitian) 
polynomials. However, SCHRODINGER has shown that in the four- 
dimensional space-time serious difficulties appear. 



134 THE CONCEPTUAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 

Quite independently from these considerations, the elimination of 
the infinities with the help of the factor exp ( D) has been 
investigated by PAIS and UHLENBEGK (1950) and others. 

The most radical change in the structure of the theory has been 
proposed by HEISENBERG (1943). Convinced of the existence of an 
absolute length a~io~ 13 cm. or an absolute time r = a\c ~ 
io" 24 sec, he doubts that the usual description of a physical system 
with the help of a HAMILTON function has a meaning at all for 
space- and time-intervals smaller than a and r.What we really can 
observe are only alterations, in time-intervals long compared with r. 
If the state of the system at a time ^ is described by ^(^), that at 
t 2 by ^(tfg), it is legitimate to assume that in the equation 



the transition operator S(t ly J 2 ) has a physical meaning for t 2 x 
> T, in particular its value S( oo, oo). This operator is usually 
called the S-matrix. For instance, in a collision process we observe 
particles before and after the collision, and we are interested only 
to know the distribution after the collision if that before is known. 
HEISENBERG maintains that all attempts to describe the collision 
process itself should be abandoned. 

The postulate of relativistic invariance introduces strange para- 
doxes in this theory. The temporal order of events, and thus the 
cause-effect relation, breaks down for short time intervals; for 
instance, a particle may be absorbed before the creating collision 
has taken place. But HEISENBERG (1951) has made it plausible that 
these anomalies may be unobservable in principle because of the 
atomistic structure of the instruments. 

According to the principle of correspondence the S matrix theory 
must go over into an ordinary Hamiltonian theory for cases where 
the absolute length or time play no important part. HEISENBERG- 
comes to the conclusion that very likely the current assumptions 
about interactions are not sufficient. These lead to Hamiltonians 
which can be re-normalized in the sense described above. Actually 
there are indications that a more thorough non-linearity is needed. 
In a recent paper (1952) he discusses the process of meson showers- 
from this standpoint and uses a type of non-linear field theory which 
I found about twenty years ago and published in collaboration with 
Infeld (1933, 1934). It is a modification of MAXWELL C S electrodyna- 
mics in which the self energy of the electron is finite. MIE had 
shown already in 1912 that the equations of the electromagnetic 
field can be formally generalized by replacing the linear relations 
between the two pairs of field vectors E, B and D, H by non linear 



THE CONCEPTUAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 135 

ones. Yet he did not specify these relations, and thus his formalism 
remained empty. 

The idea which I applied to it is a special case of what WHITTAKER 
(1949) has called the principle of impotence. If research leads to an 
obstacle which in spite of all efforts cannot be removed, theory 
declares it as insurmountable in principle. Well known examples are 
the first and second theorems of thermodynamics which are derived 
from the impossibility of perpetual motion of the first and second 
kind. Other examples are relativity, where the impossibility of 
material and signal velocities larger than the velocity of light is 
declared, and the uncertainty relations of quantum mechanics, 
which forbid the simultaneous determination of position and velocity 
and of similar pairs. 

In the case of the electromagnetic field the self energy can be 
made finite by prohibiting the increase of E the electric vector 
beyond a certain limit, the absolute field. This can be done by 
imitating relativity where the classical Lagrangian of a free particle 
= %mv 2 is replaced by mc 2 [i (i z> 2 /c 2 )*L ^ rom which 
v < c follows. In a similar way the Lagrangian density of MAXWELL'S 
electrodynamics can be replaced by a square root expression. Thus 
a finite self energy of a point charge is obtained which represents 
not only the inertial mass but also, as SCHRODINGER has shown, the 
gravitational mass. 

A more important asset of this theory seems to me the estimate of 
the fine structure constant, obtained by HEISENBERG and his pupils 
EULER and KOGKEL (1935, 1936) and confirmed by WEISSKOPF 
(1936), by comparing the lowest non-linear terms of it with the 
corresponding terms of DIRAC'S theory of holes, which are due to 
what is called a 'polarization of the vacuum'. The result is i/a 
= kje* = 82, which, though still much too small, is of the right 
order of magnitude. This method appears to me the only rational 
attempt to derive the number i/a = 137. 

That the non-linear theory has not found favour is partly due to 
the difficulty of quantization, partly to an objection raised by 
HEITLER which at the time seemed to me convincing. He said that 
a classical theory of the electron, which takes PLANCK'S constant h 
as negligible but the charge e as finite, is meaningless because 
i/a = hc/e 2 = 137 is a large number. 

Now HEISENBERG, in search of a non-linear field theory as 
limiting case of his S matrix formalism, took over that square root 
method and applied it to the meson field produced by a nucleon. 
But he applied it to quite a different type of problem, namely the 
meson showers produced by a nuclear collision. Here HEITLER'S 



136 THE CONCEPTIONAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 

objection becomes insignificant. If HEISENBERG'S procedure is 
analysed, it is seen that it does not rest on the limit h -> o, but 
JV - co where JV is the number of quanta involved. In fact BOHR 
had both these cases in mind right from the beginning when he 
formulated the transition from quantum theory to its classical limit. 
(The same consideration justifies the estimate of the fine structure 
constant, mentioned above.) 

HEISENBERG considers the collision of two nucleons, each being 
the source of a meson field, obeying his non-linear field equations. 
For a very high collision energy the number of meson quanta will 
be very large, hence the application of a classical wave equation 
permitted. The total energy carried by this wave i/r can be repre- 
sented by an integral over all wave vectors k of a function w(k); 
if tt(k) is divided by the energy quantum hv, where v = c \ k | is 
the frequency of the wave k, and the result integrated over all k one 
obtains the total number JV* of quanta emitted. In this way it can 
be shown that for a non-linear theory of the type described multiple 
meson production is possible and the value of JV can be estimated. 

Now this idea of multiple showers is sharply contradicted, in 
particular by HEITLER, who thinks that the observations can be 
explained in terms of plural production. The experiments are made 
not with two colliding nucleons but with one nucleon hitting a 
nucleus; then a cascade of nucleons and mesons will develop and 
thus a shower of mesons mixed with nucleons or larger splinters 
appear. HEITLER, in a letter to me, quotes experimental investiga- 
tions by TERREAUX (1951, 1952) as confirming the cascade theory, 
and some unpublished work by McCusKER. Showers were produced 
in layers of carbon and of a paraffin containing equal numbers of 
G atoms; thus the effect of the H atoms (proton-proton collisions) 
can be deduced, and the result was that up to 3 x io 10 eV no 
multiple production was observed. This is, however, in strict contra- 
diction to experiments made by HAXEL and collaborators, of which 
I have learned through my correspondence with HEISENBERG; here 
layers of carbon and paraffin of equal mass (equal number of 
nucleons) were investigated with the help of counters which recorded 
showers of three or more penetrating particles. 

The result is that the H atoms have their full share in the multiple 
production. HEISENBERG has further sent me a photograph of a 
shower containing about 16 mesons, but no heavy track. He inter- 
prets it as evidence for multiple production, but it might just as 
well be' a nuclear cascade in which the heavy particles are by chance 
all neutrons. 
Just a few days ago my attention was directed to a paper by 



THE CONCEPTIONAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 137 

VIDALE and SCHEIN (1951) which, if confirmed, would settle the 
dispute. Self-registering instruments were carried by balloons to 
more than 90,000 feet altitude and showers in liquid hydrogen 
observed with counters. The results seemed to be in favour of 
multiple production, but the assumption made that the primary 
particles are nucleons (protons) is not certain at all. I have the 
impression that HEISENBERG'S audacious ideas are in the right 
direction, and this direction is obviously not backward, but forward 
to new abstractions, to a new style of thinking. 

I have so far only considered the conceptual problems arising 
from the microscopic world of elementary particles. Of equal 
importance are the problems of the macrocosmos which are inti- 
mately connected with general relativity. However, as I am not an 
expert in astrophysics and cosmology, I wish to make only a few 
remarks about this vast subject. 

Since EDDINGTON'S time we have been aware of the intimate 
relation between the atomistic world and the universe. EINSTEIN 
himself has made incessant attempts to understand the existence of 
particles and quanta as singularities of a united gravitational 
electromagnetic field. But I cannot believe that by singling out 
these two types of field a real unification can be achieved, quite 
apart from my conviction that quantum theory cannot be reduced 
to classical concepts. The most important idea, due to astrophysics, 
is the suggestion of spontaneous creation of matter. There are two 
versions of it, one by HOYLE, BONDI and GOLD (1948), who assume 
the permanent creation of hydrogen atoms uniformly in space, the 
other by JORDAN (1944), who assumes the instantaneous creation of 
whole stars or even galaxies, which then appear as super novae. 
Both theories have in common that they oppose the idea of a history 
of the universe, as suggested by the simplest interpretation of the 
recession of the nebulae (Hubble effect), namely an expanding 
universe, beginning, about 2,000 million years ago, in a highly 
concentrated state. Instead, both theories aim at describing the 
world as being in a steady state, where just as much matter is 
created as disappears in infinity (that is when it reaches the velocity 
of light). 

Both authors have suggested modifications of EINSTEIN'S field 
equations. HOYLE'S original theory did not follow the usual 
Lagrangian pattern, which secures the compatability of the cause- 
effect relation and of general relativity. Thus he, strangely enough, 
seemed to be prepared to sacrifice general relativity. McCREA (1951) 
has recently shown that this is not necessary, and that by assuming 
the existence of a kind of universal cosmic pressure (apart from that 



138 THE CONCEPTIONAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 

due to ordinary matter and energy) the relativistic equations can 
be preserved. 

JORDAN'S theory is based on an idea of DIRAC (1937) according to 
which the gravitational constant K is actually not a constant, but a 
(slowly changing) eleventh field variable, in addition to the 10 
components g^ of the gravitational field. This suggestion is not at 
all arbitrary, but based on strong arguments concerning the order 
of magnitude of the cosmic constants. JORDAN has further shown 
that from the standpoint of group theory his equations are preferable 
to those with constant /c, and that the creation of matter in bulk, 
as suggested by him, does not mean a violation of the conservation 
law of energy, but only a transformation of gravitational energy 
into material substance. 

Both types of hypotheses are supported by a considerable amount 
of empirical evidence which consists, of course, not so much in 
direct observations, but in developing a coherent and rational 
picture of the universe in agreement with the facts. 1 am unable to 
decide who may be nearer to the truth. 

I have mentioned these ideas because the future theory of matter 
cannot by-pass the cosmological point of view. Very likely I have 
omitted to mention other important suggestions, for which I 
apologize. 

Returning to the first sentences of this lecture, I may say that 
much has been achieved during the fifty years since my student days ; 
many problems have been solved which about 1900 had not even 
been formulated. But the present time seems to offer still more 
puzzles, and perhaps harder ones. My aim was to show that our 
conceptual armoury will be capable of dealing with them, provided 
we do not look back to the good old times, but forward to new 
adventures of discovery and explanation. 



REFERENCES 

BHABHA, H. J. (1945) Rev. Mod. Phys., 17, 200; (1948) Report of 1946 Inter- 
national Conference, I: Fundamental Particles (London: The Physical 
Society), 22; (1949) Rev. Mod. Phys., 21, 451; (1951) Phys. Rev., 
77, 665. 

BLOKHINTZEV, D. (1956) Upsekki fisick nauk, 42, 76; (1951) Ibid., 44, 104. 

BOHM, D. (1952) Phys. Rev., 85, 166, 180. 

BONDI, H. and GOLD, T. (1948) Mon. Not. Roy. Astr. Soc., 108, 252. 

BORN, M. (1933), Nature, Lond., 132, 282; (1934) Proc. Roy. Soc. A, 143, 
4*0; ( J 953) && 3- Phil Sci., 4, No. 14, 95. 

BORN, M. and GREEN, H. S. (1949) Proc. Roy. Soc. Edinb. A, 62, 470. 

BORN, M. and INFELD, L. (1933) Nature, Lond. a 132, 970, 1004; (1934) 

Proc. Roy. Soc. A, 144, 425. 



THE CONCEPTIONAL SITUATION IN PHYSICS 139 

DE BROGUE, L. (1926) C. R. Acad. Sci., Paris, 188, 447; (1927) Ibid., 184, 
2 73; l8 5> 380; (1952) see De Broglie, Physicien et Penseur (Paris: A. 
Michel). 

DIRAC, P. A. M. (1937) Nature, Lord., 139, 323; (1951) Proc. Roy. Soc. A, 
209, 291; (1952) Ibid. 9 212, 330. 

Du MOND, J. W. M. and COHEN, E. R. (1951) Phys. Rev., 82, 555. 

EDDINGTON, A. (1928) Proc. Roy. Soc. A, 121, 524; 122, 358; see also 
Relativity Theory of Protons and Electrons (Cambridge: University 
Press, 1936). & 7 

EULER, H. (1936) Ann. Phys., Lpz., 26, 398. 

EULER, H. and HEISENBERG, W. (1936) Phys., 98, 714. 

EULER, H. and KOCKEL, B. (1935) Naturwiss., 23, 246. 

FIERZ, M. (1939) Helv. Phys. Acta, 12, 3. 

FIERZ, M. and PAULI, W. (1939) Proc. Roy. Soc. A, 173, 211. 

FRENKEL, J. (1950) Upsekkifaick nauk, 42, 69; (1951) Ibid., 44, no, 

HEISENBERG, W. (1943) Phys., 120, 313, 673; (1951) Festschrift Akad. d. 
Wiss. Gottingen, p. 50; (1952) . Phys., 133, 65. 

HOYLE, F. (1948) Mon. Not. Roy. Astr. Soc., 108, 252. 

JORDAN, P. (1944) Phys. ., 45, 183; (1947) Die Herkwft der Sterne (Stutt- 
gart: Hirzel); (1949) Nature, Lord., 164, 637; (1952) Schwerkraft 
wnd Weltall (Braunschweig: Vieweg). 

KARPLUS, R. and KLEIN, A. (1952) Phys. Rev., 85, 972. 

KOCKEL, B. (1937) Phys., 107, 153. 

LAMB, W. E., Jr. and RETHERFORD, R. C. (1947) Phys. Rev., 72, 241; 

XT (1949) Ibid., 75, 1325, 1332; (1950) Ibid., 79> 549- 

McCREA, W. H. (1951) Proc. Roy. Soc. A, 206, 562; (1951) J. Trans. Victoria 
Inst., 83, 105. 

MADELUNG, E. (1927) . Phys., 40, 322. 

MIE, G. (1912) Ann. Phys., Lpz., 37, 511; 39, i; (1913) Ibid., 40, i. 

MILLER, G. (1951) D. KgL Danske Vidensk. Selskab, Mat-fys. Medd., Nos. 
21 and 22. 

NEUMANN, J. VON (1932) Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik 
(Berlin: Springer Verlag), pp. 167-171. 

PAIS, A. and UHLENBECK, G. E. (1950) Phys. Rev., 79, 145. 

PEIERLS, R. and McMANUs, H. (1948) Proc. Roy. Soc. A, 195, 323. 

RAYSKI, J. (1951) Proc. Roy. Soc. A, 206, 575; (1951) Phil. Mag., 42, 1289. 

SCHRODINGER, E. (1952) Brit. J. Phil. Sci., 3, 109, 233. 

SCHWINGER, J. (1948) Phys. Rev., 74, 1439; (1949) Ibid., 75, 651, 76, 790. 

STUCKELBERG, E. C. G. and PETERMANN, A. (1951) Phys. Rev., 82 548; 
(1951) Helv. Phys. Acta, 24, 317. 

TERREAUX, CH. (1951) Helv. Phys. Acta, 24, 551; (1952) Nuovo Cimento, 

9> i29- 

TOMANAGA, S. (1946) Prog. Theor. Phys., i, 27, and subsequent papers. 
VBDALE, M. L. and SCHEIN, M. (1951) Nuovo Cimento, 8, i. 
WEISSKOPF, V. (1936) KgL Danske. Vidensk. Selskab., Mat-fys. Medd., 14, 6. 
WEIZSACKER, K. F., VON (1949) Die Geschichte der Natur (Stuttgart: Hirzel); 

(1951) gum Weltbild der Physik (Stuttgart: Hirzel). 
WHTTTAKER, E. T. (1949) From Euclid to Eddington (Cambridge: University 

Press). 
YUKAWA, H. (1949) Phys. Rev., 77, 219. 



THE INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM 
MECHANICS 

[First published in The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol. IV, 1953.] 

following pages are a reply to ERWIN SCHRODINGER'S article, 
'Are There Quantum Jumps? Parts I and II', published in 
August and November, 1952, in this Journal A discussion on this 
subject was to be held in the meeting of the Philosophy of Science 
Group on December 8th, 1952, and I was asked to open it. I 
accepted this honour rather reluctantly, for I find it awkward to 
display in public a disagreement on a fundamental question with 
one of my best and oldest friends. Yet I had several motives for 
accepting the challenge: The first is my conviction that no dis- 
crepancy of opinion on scientific questions can shake our friendship. 
The second, that other good and old friends of the same standing as 
SCHRODINGER, such as NIELS BOHR, HEiSENBERG and PAUL!, share 
my opinion. My third, and the most important reason for entering 
into this discussion of SCHRODINGER'S publication is that by its 
undeniable literary merits, the width of its historical and philoso- 
phical horizon, and the ingenious presentation of the arguments, 
it may have a confusing effect on the mind of those who, without 
being physicists, are interested in the general ideas of physics. 

The discussion on December 8th was rather frustrated by 
SCHRODINGER'S absence, due to serious illness. I read my prepared 
introduction and answered questions. But this was, of course, not 
fair play to SCHRODINGER himself. Therefore I have to state my case 
in print. The following is a slightly enlarged version of my intro- 
duction to the discussion. As such, it covers not in the least all points 
made by SCHRODINGER, but only those which seem to me suited for 
a debate amongst philosophers. 

i. SCHRODINGER'S CASE RESTATED 

The whole discrepancy is not so much an internal matter of 
physics, as one of its relation to philosophy and human knowledge 
in general. Any one of us theoretical physicists, including SCHROD- 
INGER, confronted with an actual problem would use the same, or at 
least equivalent mathematical methods, and if we should obtain 
concrete results our prediction and our prescription for the experi- 
mental verification would be practically the same. The difference of 

140 



THE INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 141 

opinion appears only if a philosopher comes along and asks us : Now 
what do you really mean by your words, how can you speak about 
electrons to be sometimes particles, sometimes waves, and so on? 
Such questions about the real meanings of our words are just as 
important as the mathematical formalism. SGHRODINGER challenges 
the use of words in the current interpretation of the formalism; he 
suggests a simple, puristic language and maintains that it can cope 
with the situation. We answer, that this purism is not only perfectly 
impracticable by its clumsiness, but also quite unjustifiable from the 
historical, psychological, epistemological, philosophical standpoint. 
I suppose you have all read SCHRODINGER'S paper. What he 
maintains can be condensed in a few sentences: The only reality in 
the physical world is waves. There are no particles and there are no 
energy quanta Av; they are an illusion due to a wrong interpretation 
of resonance phenomena of interfering waves. These waves are 
connected with integers in a way well known from the vibrations of 
strings and other musical instruments, and these integers have 
deluded the physicist into believing that they represent numbers of 
particles. But there is a special resonance law," characteristic of 
quantum mechanics, according to which the sum of the eigenfre- 
quencies of two interacting systems remains constant. This has been 
interpreted by the physicists as the conservation law of energy 
applied to quanta of particles. But there are no such things. Any 
attempt to describe the physical phenomena in terms of particles 
without contradicting the well-established wave character of their 
propagation in space, leads to impossible, unacceptable conceptions 
like the assumption of timeless quantum jumps of particles from one 
stationary state to another. Moreover, if you try to describe a gas 
composed of particles you are compelled to deprive them of their 
individuality; if you write tlie symbol (A, B) to express that A is here 
at one place, B there at another, the two situations (A, B) and 
(B, A) are not only physically indistinguishable, but represent 
statistically only one case, not two, as common sense would demand. 
All these and many other difficulties disappear if you abandon the 
particle concept and use only the idea of waves. 

2. ARE THERE ATOMS? 

It is only a few years ago since SCHRODINGER published a paper 
under the title '2,500 Years of Quantum Mechanics', in which he 
stressed the point that PLANCK'S discovery of the quantum was the 
culmination of a continuous development starting with the Greek 
philosophers LEUQPPUS and DEMOCRTTUS, the founders of the atom- 
istic school. At that time he obviously thought the idea that matter is 



1^2 THE INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 

composed of atoms, ultimate indivisible particles, a great achieve- 
ment. Now he rejects the same idea, because the execution of the 
programme leads to some grinding noise in our logical machinery. 

It is this anti-atomistic attitude which appears to me the weakest, 
in fact quite indefensible, point in SCHRODINGER'S arguments against 
the current interpretation of quantum mechanics. All other points 
are of a more technical nature, but this one is fundamental. SCHROD- 
INGER opens both parts of his paper by a section entitled The 
Cultural Background', in which he accuses the theoretical physicists 
of our time of having lost the feeling of historical continuity and 
overestimating their own achievements as compared with those of 
their forerunners. He gives examples of such defaults which I do not 
wish to defend, but I think that he himself offers an example which 
is even worse. 

The atomistic idea, since its revival through DANIEL BERNOULLI 
(1738) in the kinetic theory of gases and through DALTON (1808) in 
chemistry, has been so fertile and powerful that SCHRODINGER'S 
attempt to overthrow it appears to me almost presumptuous, and in 
any case an obvious violation of historical continuity. 

3. WAVES INSTEAD OF ATOMS 

Such a violation would be justified if he could supply a better and 
more powerful substitute. That is exactly what he claims. He says 
that everything in physics, and in chemistry as well, can be described 
in terms of waves. The ordinary reader will certainly understand this 
as meaning: ordinary waves of some not specified substance in 
ordinary 3-dimensional space. Only in the last section of Part II 
(p. 241) does he indicate that one has in general to do with waves 
in a multi-dimensional space, but e To enlarge on this in general terms 
would have little value 5 . I think this is a very essential point which 
must be discussed. But before doing so I wish to say that I regard 
SCHRODINGER'S wave mechanics as one of the most admirable feats in 
the whole history of theoretical physics. I also know that his motive 
was his dislike of BOHR'S theory of stationary states and quantum 
jumps, which he wished to replace by something more reasonable. 
I quite understand his triumph when he succeeded in interpreting 
those horrible stationary states as innocuous proper vibrations and 
the mysterious quantum numbers as the analogy to the numbers of 
musical overtones. He is in love with this idea. 

I, of course, have no personal attachment to the waves. I have 
been involved, together with HEISENBERG and JORDAN, in the 
development of another method, matrix mechanics, in which station- 
ary states and quantum jumps have a natural place. But I have no 



THE INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 143 

special preference for the matrix theory. As soon as SCHRODINGER'S 
wave equation was published, I applied it to the theory of collisions; 
this suggested to me the interpretation of the wave function as 
probability amplitude. I welcomed SCHRODINGER'S elegant proof of 
the formal equivalence of wave mechanics and matrix mechanics. 
I do not plead in favour of matrix mechanics, or its generalisation 
due to DIRAG, nor do I attack wave mechanics. I wish to refute the 
exaggerated claims of SCHRODINGER'S paper from which the non- 
expert reader must get the impression that all phenomena can be 
described in terms of ordinary waves in ordinary space. 

The physicist knows that this is not true. In the case of a 2-body 
problem (like the hydrogen atom) one can split the wave equation 
into two, one for the motion ofriie centre of mass, the other for the 
relative motion, both in 3-dimensional space. But already, in the 
case of the 3-body problem (for instance, the helium atom, one 
nucleus with two electrons) this is impossible; one needs a 6-dimen- 
sional space for the relative motion. In the case of JV particles one 
needs a 3 (JV-i) -dimensional space which only in singular cases is 
reducible to a smaller number of dimensions. 

But this means that the claim of simplicity and of 'Anschaulich- 
keit', the possibility of seeing the process in space, is illusory.* In 
fact a multi-dimensional wave function is nothing but a name for the 
abstract quantity ^ of the formalism, which by some of the modern 
theorists also goes under the more learned title of c state vector in the 
Hilbert space 5 . Any attempt to describe phenomena, except the 
simplest ones, in terms of these multi-dimensional wave functions, 
means the formulation of the concise contents of mathematical 
formulae in words of ordinary language. This would be not only 
extremely clumsy but practically impossible. 

In fact, SCHRODINGER makes no attempt in this direction. All his 
examples are chosen in such a way that a 3-dimensional representa- 
tion is possible. He restricts himself to cases which in the particle 
language correspond to independent (non-interacting) particles. 
Then he shows that these particles are not behaving as good, well 
bred particles, like grains of sand, should behave. 

4. WHY ATOMS ARE INDISPENSABLE 

I think that in spite of these abnormities the concept of particle 
cannot be discarded. 

* In another article which has recently appeared ('Louis de Broglie, Physicien et 
Penseur' ed. ALBIN MICHEL, Paris, 1952) SCHRSDINGER remarks that the 3- 
dimensionality of the waves can be saved with the help of second quantisation. 
But the 'Anschaulichkeit* is then also lost and the statistical character of the 
v-function is introduced on an even deeper and more abstract level. 



144 THE INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 

As I said already, for the calculations of the theoretical physicist 
the whole question is almost irrelevant. But if he wants to connect 
his results with experimental facts, he has to describe them in terms 
of physical apparatus. These consist of bodies, not of waves. Thus 
at some point the wave description, even if it were possible, would 
have to be connected with ordinary bodies. The laws governing the 
motion of these tangible bodies are undoubtedly those of Newtonian 
mechanics. Thus the wave theory has necessarily to provide means 
to translate its results into the language of mechanics of ordinary 
bodies. If this is done systematically, the connecting link is matrix 
mechanics, or one of its generalisations. I cannot see how this transi- 
tion from wave mechanics to ordinary mechanics of solid bodies can 
possibly be avoided. 

Let us look at the matter the other way round, starting from 
ordinary bodies. These can be divided into parts, and sub-divided 
into still smaller parts. The Greek idea was that this procedure has 
an end somewhere, when parts become particles, atoms, which are 
indivisible. 

Modern theory has modified this view to some degree, but I need 
not go into details which you all know. The parts of a substance 
obtained by division and subdivision are of the same physical nature 
until you approach the chemical atom. This is not indivisible, but its 
parts are of a different nature, particles of a more subtle quality, 
nucleons and electrons. Then we discover that the smallest units, 
the chemical. atoms and still more the nucleons and electrons, have 
not only different qualities, but decidedly strange qualities, strange 
if you expect always to find the same as you are accustomed to. They 
behave differently from the powder particles into which you have 
first ground your material. They have no individuality, their 
position and velocity can be determined only with a restricted 
accuracy (according to HEISENBERG'S uncertainty relation) and so 
on. Shall we then say, well, there are no particles any more, we must 
regretfully abandon the use of this simple and attractive picture ? 

We can do it if we take a strictly positivistic standpoint: The 
only reality is the sense impressions. All the rest are 'constructs' of 
the mind. We are able to predict, with the help of the mathematical 
apparatus of quantum mechanics, what the experimentalist will 
observe under definite experimental conditions, the current shown 
by a galvanometer, the track in a photographic plate. But it is 
meaningless to ask what there is behind the phenomena, waves or 
particles or what else. Many physicists have adopted this standpoint. 
I dislike it thoroughly, and so does SGHRODINGER. For he insists that 
there is something behind the phenomena, the sense impressions, 



THE INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 45 

namely waves moving in a still scantily explored medium. Recently 
an American physicist, BOHM, has taken the opposite standpoint; he 
claims that he can interpret the whole of quantum mechanics in 
terms of ordinary particles with the help of parameters describing 
unobservable 'concealed' processes. 

5. HOW TO MODIFY THE ATOMISTIC CONCEPT 

I think' that neither of these extremist views can be maintained. 
The current interpretation of quantum theory which tries to recon- 
cile both aspects of the phenomena, waves, and particles, seems to 
me on the right way. It is impossible to give here an account of the 
intricate logical balance. I wish only to illustrate the manner in 
which the particle concept is adapted to new conditions, by some 
examples from other fields, where a similar situation is found. It is 
of course no new situation that a concept in its original meaning 
turns out too narrow. But instead of abandoning it, science has 
applied another method, which is by far more fertile and satisfac- 
tory. Consider the example of the number concept. Number means 
originally what we now call integer, i, 2, 3 ... KRONEKER has said 
that God has made the integers, while the rest are human work. 
Indeed, if you define numbers as the means of counting things, even 
rational numbers like 2/3 or 4/5 are not numbers any more. The 
Greeks extended the concept of number to them by restricting the 
consideration to a finite set where a smallest unit (the greatest 
common denominator) can be found. But then they made the 
fundamental discovery that the diagonal of the square (of the side i), 
which we write y's, is not a number in this sense; but great as their 
logical genius was, they did not make the next constructive step. 
They had not the pluck to generalise the number concept in such a 
way that <\/2 was included, but invented an ingenious yet rather 
clumsy geometrical method to deal with such cases. This was the 
stumbling block which retarded mathematics for about 2,000 years. 
Only in modern times the necessary generalisation of the idea of 
number was made so as to include these things such as *y/2, still 
called irrational. But then further generalisations followed, the 
introduction of algebraic, transcendental, complex numbers. You 
cannot count with the help of these. But they have other, more 
formal properties in common with the integers, and the latter are a 
special case. Similar generalisations of concepts are common in 
mathematics. But they appear also in physics. Sound was certainly 
defined as that which you can hear, light as that which you can see. 
But we speak now of inaudible sound (ultrasonics) and invisible light 
(infrared, ultraviolet). Even in ordinary life this process of extension 



146 THE INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 

of meaning is going on. Take the concept of democracy which 
originally meant the organisation of government in the Greek city 
states where the citizens assembled in the market place to discuss 
and decide their problems; today, it is used for the government of 
gigantic states by parliamentary representation. In Russia it even 
means something which we should regard as the opposite of 
democracy. Therefore we had better return to the safe ground of 
science. 

I maintain that the use of the concept of particles has to be 
justified in the same way. It must satisfy two conditions: First it must 
share some (not in the least all) properties of the primitive idea of 
particle (to be part of matter in bulk, of which it can be regarded 
as composed), and secondly this primitive idea must be a special, 
or better,, limiting case. 

Now it is exactly in this sense that the particle concept is used in 
quantum mechanics. I cannot see any objection to it. SCHRODINGER'S 
examples seem to me of the kind which prohibited the Greeks from 
admitting the representation of the diagonal of the unit square as a 
number; it differs from all possible ratios of integers, as can easily be 
seen. The effect of accepting SCHRODINGER'S thesis would perhaps not 
be equally portentous, because he does not attack the formal theory, 
only its philosophical background. He would even allow the 
physicists and chemists to use the particle language with a proper 
e as if. Imagine a textbook of chemistry written according to this 
prescription. Water behaves as if it were composed of molecules 
H 2 O, each of which again reacts as if composed of two H-atoms and 
one O-atom. But when we continue, each H-atom has properties 
as if it were composed of a nucleus and an electron, we transgress the 
permitted domain of c as if', for here SCHRODINGER insists that there is 
no particle called electron but a charged wave around the nucleus 
which itself actually is also a wave of some kind. But when we then 
wish to deal with a photo-ionisation of this H-atom we have to fall 
back to his *as if 3 to describe the discontinuous recording of a Geiger 
counter. 

All our language, in life and science, is growing through general- 
isations of concepts, which sometimes are first considered to be e as 
ifs% but then are amalgamated and become legitimate words in 
their own right. For this end it is necessary to fix the rules of their 
employment in a reasonable manner. This process, in which NIELS 
BOHR has played a leading part, is still going on, and, I think, with 
fair success. One can, of course, pick out points where some logical 
hardness or roughness appears, and that is what SCHRODINGER has 
done. 



THE INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 147 

On the other hand, SCHRODINGER cannot avoid the use of the 
words particles or atoms. They appear in many of his examples; 
otherwise his words would convey no meaning. For instance, when 
he speaks about quantum statistics of gases he has to discuss a wave 
equation in a multi-dimensional space. This equation has, of course, 
a simple meaning if considered from the particle standpoint ; it is the 
wave-mechanical translation of the law of conservation of kinetic 
energy for n particles. Now SCHRODINGER is compelled to disown 
this translation, the lovely child of his brain, for otherwise he would 
admit that there are, in some sense, particles. He has to take the 3/2- 
dimensional wave equation as something given to him by inspiration 
and confirmed by experiments. This is a distortion of historical facts. 

6. COLLISIONS 

Though I wish to avoid technical details I have to say a few words 
about the problem of collisions which SCHRODINGER discusses in 
several places (Sections 6 and 8). He finds the usual quantum- 
mechanical treatment faulty, he accuses the physicists of loose 
speech, he preaches to them that 'Science is not a soliloquy' and 
prophesies that their work will be forgotten in 2 3 ooo years' time, 
while that of ARCHIMEDES or GALILEO has survived similar periods. 
In a letter to me he maintains that 'almost all great successes of 
quantum mechanics consist of the satisfactory calculation of ex- 
tended systems of eigenvalues (of the energy), each from a definite, 
more or less plausible assumption about the nature of the system in 
question (Hamilton operator), and have nothing at all to do with the 
statistical interpretation. On the other side there are the scattering 
experiments (calculation of differential cross-sections of interaction 
and things like that) . Only the Klein-Nishina formula is apparently 
quantitatively confirmed. (The latter represents the scattering of 
light, or photons, by an electron.) 5 He further doubts that the 
statistical interpretation, which I have first suggested and which has 
been formulated in the most general way by VON NEUMANN, is 
applicable to these cases at all. 

To this I reply that in principle we know about the eigenvalues 
of the energy (Hamiltonian) of material systems only from experi- 
ments about emission, absorption, scattering of light or electrons. 
These processes are all due to the coupling of the system considered 
with a 'messenger' field (the electromagnetic or photon field, or DE 
BROGLIE'S electron field) and it seems to me quite arbitrary to pick 
out the scattering as less reputable than the other two effects. 
Further, a look into the literature, for instance, the well-known book 
by MOTT and MASSEY, or the important articles by NIELS BOHR, on 



148 THE INTERPRETATION Of QUANTUM MECHANICS 

the penetration of particles through matter and innumerable other 
papers and books, shows that the number of more or less quantitative 
confirmations of the quantum-statistical scattering laws is very large, 
and that there are qualitative confirmations of a particularly con- 
vincing kind. Even in nuclear physics, where the knowledge of the 
interaction law (Hamiltonian) is doubtful and scanty, the principles 
of the statistical theory have been used with great success, of which 
the atomic bomb is one very impressive example. 

Concerning SCHRODINGER'S scepticism about the applicability of 
the general scheme for transitions (quantum jumps) to the case of 
collisions I am unable to follow his reasoning. He describes the 
procedure as if a collision were a transition between two states of 
different energy. In fact the typical 'elastic 9 collision is a transition 
between states of equal energy but different momentum vectors. 
My original method dealing with this case avoids any reference to 
time; it considers the steady state of an incoming wave (representing 
a beam of e messenger' particles), transformed by its interaction with 
an atom into a spherical wave (representing the out-going, scattered 
particles). In this way of considering the process there is no initial 
and no final state, concepts which seem to SCHRODINGER ill-defined. 
They appear in DIRAG'S version of the collision theory which he 
developed in order to consider collisions as a special case of the 
general theory of transitions in time (formulated first in my papers on 
'adiabatic invariants' and in DIRAG'S simultaneous publications, and 
perfected by J. v. NEUMANN). But DIRAG has shown that his method 
(involving time) is mathematically equivalent to the 'stationary, 
method; the conceptual difficulties which worry SCHRODINGER are 
therefore only a matter of careful formulation. 

Another objection which he raises refers to the approximation 
method which I introduced in my early papers to solve the very 
complicated mathematical equations of scattering. This method 
gives reasonable, and often well-confirmed, results in the first 
approximation; but higher approximations are difficult to obtain, 
and if they can be constructed there are cases where they lead to 
divergent integrals. However, there are other methods which use 
quite different expansions (for instance, in terms of spherical 
harmonics and Bessel functions) and lead to results which are 
mathematically sound and well confirmed by experiments. 

I cannot see at all that these purely mathematical objections have 
anything to do with the question of 'particles-waves', or 'quantum 
jumps'. For if we accept SGHRODINGER'S standpoint that there are 
no particles, only waves, the scattering calculations would be 
exactly the same as before; the only difference would be that we 



THE INTERPRETATION o QUANTUM MECHANICS 149 

would speak about the intensity of the incoming and the outgoing 
wave (electromagnetic, electronic, pro tonic, etc., wave, as the case 
may be), and omit to interpret this intensity as the probability of 
the appearance of particles. The real problem raised by SCHROD- 
INGER is whether this probability interpretation is significant. His 
mathematical scruples have nothing to do with it. To decide this 
significant question, consider, for instance, RUTHERFORD'S experi- 
ments about the scattering of a-rays by nuclei. Here, by a kind 
of lucky mathematical co-incidence, the classical calculation (using 
particles obeying the laws of Newtonian mechanics) and the wave- 
mechanical calculation (which can be performed rigorously in this 
case) give the same result. This result is confirmed by counting the 
a-particles in the incoming and in the outgoing beam (for different 
directions of scattering) . The result is completely independent of 
the method of counting, whether by scintillations of a zinc-sulphide 
screen, or by different types of counters. How does SCHRODINGER 
account for this fact? As far as I see he has no ready explanation. 
He seems to think that it is not a discontinuity in the beam which 
produces the countable events, but some feature of the counting 
instrument. But how then is it to be explained that the result is 
independent of the type of instrument, even to that degree, that 
sparks in the little crystals of the zinc-sulphide screen and gas 
tubes, connected with elaborate amplifier apparatus, count the 
same (average) number of events? Here SGHRODINGER'S bias against 
the particle idea leads him to an almost mystical attitude; he hopes 
that the future will solve this riddle in a satisfactory way. 

7. CONCLUSION 

I have refrained from discussing the statistical interpretation of 
quantum mechanics in detail. This is not a simple matter, and 
demands not only the knowledge of a complicated mathematical 
formalism, but a certain philosophical attitude: the willingness to 
sacrifice traditional concepts and to accept new ones, like BOHR'S 
principle of complementarity. I am far from saying that the present 
interpretation is perfect and final. I welcome SCHRODINGER'S attack 
against the complacency of many physicists who are accepting the 
current interpretation because it works, without worrying about the 
soundness of the foundations. Yet I do not think that SCHRODINGER 
has made a positive contribution to the philosophical problems. It 
is very awkward for me to criticise the philosophy of a friend whom 
I deeply admire as a great scholar and deep thinker. Therefore I 
shall make use of a method of defence which SCHRODINGER himself 
is not too proud to use, namely the quotation of authorities who share 



I5O THE INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 

my own opinion. I choose as my witness W. PAULI who is generally 
acknowledged to be the most critical, logically and mathematically 
exacting amongst the scholars who have contributed to quantum 
mechanics. I translate a few lines from a letter (in German) which 
I have recently received: 

Against all retrograde efforts (SCHRODINGER, BOHM, etc., and 
in a certain sense, also EINSTEIN) I am certain that the statistical 
character of the ^-function, and thus of the laws of nature 
which you have, right from the beginning, strongly stressed in 
opposition to SCHRODINGER will determine the style of the 
laws for at least some centuries. It is possible that later, for 
example in connection with the processes of life, something 
entirely new may be found, but to dream of a way back, back 
to the classical style of NEWTON-MAXWELL (and it is nothing 
but dreams which those gentlemen indulge in), that seems to 
me hopeless, off the way, bad taste. And we could add c it is 
not even a lovely dream'. 

What PAULI means by the 'style' of a conceptual structure you 
might prefer to call the philosophical attitude of a period, which 
determines the cultural background. It is here that we differ, and 
the auspices of an agreement are therefore frail. 



PHYSICAL REALITY 

[First published in Philosophical Quarterly, pp. 139-149, 1953.] 

notion of reality in the physical world has become, during 
the last century, somewhat problematic. The contrast between 
the simple and obvious reality of the innumerable instruments, 
machines, engines, and gadgets produced by our technological 
industry, which is applied physics, and of the vague and abstract 
reality of the fundamental concepts of physical science, as forces 
and fields, particles and quanta, is doubtless bewildering. There has 
already developed a gap between pure and applied science and 
between the groups of men devoted to the one or the other activity, 
a separation which may lead to a dangerous estrangement. Physics 
needs a unifying philosophy, expressible in ordinary language, to 
bridge this gulf between 'reality' as thought of in practice and in 
theory. I am not a philosopher but a theoretical physicist. I cannot 
provide a well balanced philosophy of science that would take due 
account of the ideas developed by differing schools, but I shall 
endeavour to formulate some ideas which have helped me in my 
own struggle with these problems. 

There is a school of thought amongst theoretical physicists and 
scientific philosophers which advocates a standpoint radically 
abstract. This philosophy was expressed, for instance, in the notable 
lecture given by Professor H. DINGLE to Section A of the British 
Association in Edinburgh (published in Nature, 168, 1951, p. 630) 
and I cannot explain my own standpoint better than by way of 
contrast. But in quoting extracts from DINGLE'S lecture I do not 
intend to conduct a personal controversy; these quotations serve 
only as examples suitable to develop my own differing views. Let us 
begin with the following sentence: 'The quantities with which 
physics concerns itself are not evaluations of objective properties of 
parts of the external material world; they are simply the results we 
obtain when we perform certain operations. 5 This looks like a denial 
of the existence of a pre-existing material world; it suggests that the 
physicist does not care about the real world and makes an experi- 
ment solely in order to predict the results of yet another experiment. 
Why the physicist should take the trouble to make an experiment at 
all is not explained. This question is seemingly regarded as not 
worthy of a philosopher of science. Can we avoid asking what is the 
part played in this scheme of things by the instruments, made of 



152 PHYSICAL REALITY 

steel, brass, glass, etc., carefully composed and adjusted for an 
experiment? Are they, too, no part of a pre-existing external material 
world? Are they, like electrons, atoms and fields, merely abstract 
ideas used to predict the phenomena to be observed at the next 
experiment which is again only an assembly of ghosts ? We have 
before us a standpoint of extreme subjectivism, which may rightly 
be called 'physical solipsism'. It is well-known that obstinately held 
solipsism cannot be refuted by logical argument. This much, how- 
ever, can be said, that solipsism such as this does not solve but 
evades the problem. Logical coherence is a purely negative criterion; 
no system can be accepted without it, but no system is acceptable 
just because it is logically tenable. The only positive argument in 
support of this abstract type of ultra-subjectivism is an historical 
one. It is maintained that the belief in the existence of an external 
world is irrelevant and indeed detrimental to the progress of science, 
and that what the physicist is doing can be satisfactorily understood 
only in terms of Experiences', not of the external world. 

The actual situation is very different. All great discoveries in 
experimental physics have been due to the intuition of men who 
made free use of models, which were for them not products of the 
imagination, but representatives of real things. How could an 
experimentalist work and communicate with his collaborators and 
his contemporaries without using models composed of particles, 
electrons, nucleons, photons, neutrinos, fields and waves, the con- 
cepts of which are condemned as irrelevant and futile ? 

However, there is of course some reason for this extreme stand- 
point. We have learned that a certain caution is necessary in using 
these concepts. The naive approach to the problem of reality which 
was so successful in the classical or Newtonian period, has been 
proved to be not satisfactory. Modern theories demand a reformula- 
tion. This new formulation is slowly evolving, but has probably not 
reached a final expression. I shall try to indicate the present 
tendencies. 

The first point is to remember that the word reality is part of our 
ordinary language, and hence its meaning is ambiguous like that of 
most words. There are subjective philosophies which teach that only 
the mental world is real and the physical world merely an appear- 
ance, a shadow without substance. This standpoint, though of the 
greatest philosophical interest, is outside the scope of our discussion, 
which has to do only with physical reality. Still there remain enough 
other queries. The realities of a peasant or craftsman, a merchant 
or banker, a statesman or soldier have certainly little in common. 
For each of these the most real things are those which occupy the 



PHYSICAL REALITY 153 

centre of his mind, the word real being used as almost synonymous 
with important. I wonder whether any philosophy can give a 
definition of the concept of reality that is untainted by some such 
subjective associations. The question concerning us is whether 
science can. 

This leads to the second point, stressed by DINGLE, whether the 
use of the concept and word 'reality* can be discarded without 
detriment to science. My answer is that it could only be disregarded 
by men isolated in ivory towers, remote from all experience, from 
all actual doing and observing, the type of man who becomes 
extremely absorbed in pure mathematics, metaphysics or logic. 
NIELS BOHR, who has contributed more to the philosophy of modern 
science than anybody else, has repeatedly and emphatically said 
that it is impossible to describe any actual experiment without using 
ordinary language and the concepts of naive realism. Without this 
concession no communication about facts is conceivable, even 
between the most sublime minds. And it is an essential part of this 
procedure to distinguish between ideas, projects, theories and 
formulae on the one side, and the real instruments and gadgets 
constructed according to those ideas. Here the naive use of the 
word real, the simple belief in the real existence of the material 
apparatus, is imperative. I presume that the abstract school repre- 
sented by DINGLE does not deny this, although he does not say so. 
He does, however, forbid the application of the concept of reality 
to atoms, electrons, fields, etc., terms used in the interpretation of 
observations. But where is the border between these two domains ? 
Start with a piece of a crystal, which belongs to the domain of 
crude reality, and grind it into a powder, whose particles are too 
small to be seen by the unaided eye. You have to take a microscope: 
Are the particles then less real? Still smaller particles, colloids, 
appear, properly illuminated, in the ultra-microscope, as bright 
points without structure. There is a continuous transition between 
these particles and single molecules or atoms. The ultra-microscope 
there deserts you. You then have the electron microscope with 
which you can see even large molecules. Where does that crude 
reality, in which the experimentalist lives, end, and where does the 
atomistic world, in which the idea of reality is illusion and anathema, 
begin? 

There is, of course, no such border; if we are compelled to 
attribute reality to the ordinary things of everyday life including 
scientific instruments and materials used in experimenting, we cannot 
cease doing so for objects observable only with the help of instru- 
ments. To call these objects real and part of the external world 



154 PHYSICAL REALITY 

does not, however, commit us in any way to any definite description: 
a thing may be real though very different from other things we know. 
Let me now discuss some examples which DINGLE cites to show 
the failure in physics of the concept of an objective reality. 

The first example is the kinetic theory of matter. DINGLE discusses 
the statistical method, which is not concerned with the single orbits 
of the molecules and is content to calculate averages, in order to 
represent 'observations (that is, appearances)' and he calls this 
attitude a 'betrayal of the true mission of physics according to the 
accepted philosophy. They (the physicists) were dedicated to the 
investigation of reality, which had become the investigation of the 
nature and behaviour of molecules; and instead of pursuing that, 
they occupied themselves in showing how their ignorance of reality 
could be used in order to describe mere appearances'. I have not 
been able to understand whether DINGLE thinks the whole kinetic 
theory superfluous, or whether he suggests stripping the molecules 
of their reality by calling them 'counters' or 'dummies'. For he 
makes no attempt to analyse the actual evidence provided by the 
kinetic theory for the existence of molecules. Let me sketch such an 
analysis in a few words. 

The kinetic derivation of BOYLE'S law establishes only the pos- 
sibility of an atomistic explanation, and can hardly be called 
evidence. However, the same derivation properly formulated leads 
to a definite value of the mean energy, hence of the specific heat (f R 
for monatomic gases, R being the gas constant) which no pheno- 
menological consideration could provide. The general formula for 
the mean energy contains the numbers of degrees of freedom of the 
molecules or 'dummies', to use DINGLE'S expression. The kinetic 
interpretation of the deviations from BOYLE'S laws leads to an 
estimate of the size of the molecules, which is confirmed by a quite 
different set of phenomena, the irreversible processes of heat conduc- 
tion, viscosity, diffusion. Many concepts first introduced in a 
theoretical way, like velocity distribution, free path, etc., have been 
confirmed and determined by direct measurements. The fluctua- 
tions predicted by the kinetic theory are observable in many ways, 
through the Brownian motion, the blue colour of the sky, etc. Of 
course, as DINGLE says, these are all phenomena, 'appearances', the 
molecules remaining in the background. But the essential point, not 
mentioned by DINGLE, is that the kinetic theory leads to definite 
properties of the molecules, weight, size, shape (degrees of freedom), 
mutual interaction. A small number of molecular constants de- 
termines an unlimited number of phenomenological properties, in 
virtue of the molecular hypothesis. Therefore each new property is 



PHYSICAL REALITY 155 

a confirmation of the molecular hypothesis. Amongst these predic- 
tions are such amazing feats as VON LAUE'S X-ray patterns produced 
by crystals, and the whole range of radioactive phenomena. Here 
the evidence of the reality of molecules is striking indeed, and to 
speak of a 'dummy' producing a track in a Wilson chamber or a 
photographic emulsion seems to me to say the least inadequate. 
Compare this kind of reality with the following example: You see a 
gun fired and, a hundred yards away 5 a man breaking down. How 
do you know that the bullet sticking in the man's wound has actually 
flown from the gun to the body? Nobody has seen it, in fact nobody 
could have seen it, except a scientist after cumbersome preparations, 
e.g. through the installation of a complicated optical apparatus of 
the kind ERNST MACH invented for photographing flying projectiles. 
Yet I am sure you believe that the bullet has in the short interval 
between the firing of the gun and the wounding of the man, per- 
formed a definite trajectory; you believe that it was really there 
during the interval; or are you content to say, Oh, I don't know; 
it's enough to know the phenomena of the firing and wounding. All 
things between are theoretical imagination, the bullet in flight is 
merely a "dummy" invented to account for the connection of the 
two phenomena by the laws of mechanics'. I cannot refute this 
attitude by logical reasoning. I only wish to point out that if one 
denies the existential evidence of an atomic track which can be seen, 
one is committed to denying the existence of a bullet in flight which 
cannot be seen, and of numerous similar things. 

The root of this strange denial of reality to things like molecules is 
the interpretation of the concept 'real' as meaning 'known in every 
detail 9 . This does not agree with the usual application of the word. 
We think all the 500 millions of Chinese are real, although we know 
not a single one, or perhaps a few individuals, and have not the 
slightest knowledge of their whereabouts, activities, motions, reac- 
tions. We think the Romans of Caesar's time or the Chinese during 
the life of CONFUCIUS were real although we have no possible means 
of verifying this in the way which" DINGLE demands in the case of 
molecules. Are these Romans or Chinese of the present or the past 
only dummies invented by the historians to connect phenomena? 
Which phenomena? Perhaps the words found in newspapers, in 
books, or on ancient tombstones? 

All these considerations are rather on the surface and do not 
touch the actual difficulties which physics encounters, and which 
compel us to revise our fundamental notions. DINGLE'S next example, 
relativity, leads a little nearer to these problems. He asserts that in 
accordance with the philosophy of the time, the real material world, 



156 PHVSICAL REALITY 

whether regarded as consisting of molecules or of gross bodies, was 
conceived to possess its properties by intrinsic right. Thus its con- 
stituents had a size, a mass, a velocity, and so on'. After elaborating 
this he continues: 'Now the basic requirement of the theory of 
relativity was that all these properties were almost completely 
indefinite', and he exemplifies this by the notions of length and of 
mass, which according to relativity depend on the velocity of the 
observer. The same distance measured by different observers in 
relative motion may be anything between a maximum and nothing, 
the same mass anything between a minimum and infinity. He con- 
cludes that by abandoning all attempts to assign any property at 
all to matter we can learn more and more about the relations of 
phenomena*. Now this is a misrepresentation of the theory of 
relativity, which has never abandoned all attempts to assign 
properties to matter, but has refined the method of doing so in order 
to conform with certain new experiences, such as the famous 
Michelson-Morley experiment. 

In fact this example is very well suited to get at the root of the 
matter. This root of the matter is a very simple logical distinction 
which seems to be obvious to anybody not biased by a solipsistic 
metaphysics; namely this: that often a measurable quantity is not a 
thing, but a property of its relation to other things. To give an 
example: Gut out a figure, say a circle, of a piece of cardboard and 
observe its shadow thrown by a distant lamp on a plane wall. The 
shadow of the circle will appear in general as an ellipse, and by 
turning your cardboard figure you can give to the length of an 
axis of the elliptical shadow any value between almost zero and a 
maximum. That is the exact analogue of the behaviour of length in 
relativity which in different states of motion may have any value 
between zero and a maximum. If you wish to have an analogue to 
the behaviour of mass which according to velocity may have any 
value between a minimum and infinity, take a long sausage and cut 
slices with different inclination which will be ellipses with one axis 
between a minimum and 'practical' infinity. To return to the 
shadow of the circle, it is evident that the simultaneous observation 
of the shadows on several different planes suffices to ascertain the 
fact that the original cardboard figure is a circle and to determine 
uniquely its radius. This radius is what mathematicians call an 
invariant for the transformations produced by parallel projection. In 
the same way there is an invariant of all the cross sections of a 
sausage, that with the smallest area. Most measurements in physics 
are not directly concerned with the things which interest us, but 
with some kind of projection, this word taken in the widest possible 



PHYSICAL REALITY 157 

sense. The expression co-ordinate or component can also be so used. 

The projection (the shadow in our example) is defined in relation 
to a system of reference (the walls, on which the shadow may be 
thrown). There are in general many equivalent systems of reference. 
In every physical theory there is a rule which connects the projections 
of the same object on different systems of reference, called a law of 
transformation, and all these transformations have the property of 
forming a group, i.e. the sequence of two consecutive transforma- 
tions is a transformation of the same kind. Invariants are quantities 
having the same value for any systems of reference, hence they are 
independent of the transformations. 

Now the main advances in the conceptual structure of physics 
consist in the discovery that some quantity which was regarded as 
the property of a thing is in fact only the property of a projection. 

The development of the theory of gravity is an example. Using 
modern mathematical language, the primitive (pre-Newtonian) 
conception of gravity is connected with a group of transformations 
for which the vertical, the normal to the plane surface of the earth, 
is absolutely fixed. For these transformations the size and direction 
of the force of gravity is an invariant which implies that the weight 
is an intrinsic property of the body which it carries along. The 
situation changed completely when NEWTON discovered gravity to be 
a special case of general gravitation. The group of transformations 
was extended in such a way that space became isotropic, with no 
fixed direction; gravity then became just a component of the 
gravitational force. 

The theory of relativity has continued this development. The 
transformations of classical mechanics, often called Galilean trans- 
formations, kept space and time apart. The experiences condensed 
in the theory of relativity showed that this does not agree with facts. 
One has to use a wider group, called Lorentz transformations, in 
order to introduce an intimate connection between space co-ordinates 
and time. Naturally, quantities regarded by the older theory as 
invariants, like distances in rigid systems, time intervals shown by 
clocks in different positions, masses of bodies, are now found to be 
projections, components of invariant quantities not directly acces- 
sible. Still, as in the case of the shadow, by deterniining a number of 
these components, the invariants can be found. Thus it turns out 
that the maximum length and the minimum mass are relativistic 
invariants. It would perhaps have been preferable to call these 
invariants, which are properties of bodies, by the old names length, 
time, mass, and to invent new names for the projections. But science 
is strangely conservative in such matters, and it has been agreed to 



158 PHYSICAL REALITY 

rename the invariants rest-length, proper- time, rest-mass etc., and 
keep the old expressions for the components, although these are 
now not properties of a body but of its relation to a system of 
reference. 

I think the idea of invariant is the clue to a rational concept of 
reality, not only in physics but in every aspect of the world. 

The theory of transformation groups and their invariants is a well- 
established part of mathematics. Already in 1872 the great mathe- 
matician FELIX KLEIN discussed in his famous 'Erlanger Programm' 
the classification of geometry according to this point of view; the 
theory of relativity can be regarded as an extension of this programme 
to the four-dimensional geometry of space-time. The question of 
reality in regard to gross matter has from this standpoint a clear 
and simple answer. 

The situation is more difficult in atomic physics. It is well known 
that the laws of quantum mechanics lead to a kind of indeterminacy 
expressed by HEISENBERG'S uncertainty relations. Is not this vague- 
ness, this impossibility of answering definite questions about position 
and velocity of a particle, an argument against the reality of particles 
and altogether of the objective, real world ? Here we have to reflect 
about what we mean by a particle, for instance a photon, an 
electron, a meson, a nucleon in regard to the experimental evidence; 
and again we find that these words signify definite invariants which 
can be unambiguously constructed by combining a number of 
observations. 

The underlying transformation theory, however, is rather involved, 
and I can give here only a short, sketchy indication. The essence of 
the matter can be explained with the help of ordinary light. 

The wave character of light was established by YOUNG and 
FRESNEL by showing that two beams of light, produced by splitting 
one beam, when re-united give interference fringes. Almost a 
hundred years later EINSTEIN interpreted the photo-electric effect as 
the action of light quanta or photons which on hitting a metal 
surface knock out electrons. Thus light has in addition a corpuscular 
aspect, a fact confirmed by innumerable experiments. The strange 
thing is that between these apparently contradictory concepts there 
exists a simple quantitative relation, which PLANCK had derived 
already five years earlier from the behaviour of heat radiation, 
namely E = Av, where E is the energy of the photon, v the frequency 
of the wave, and h a constant. The conceptual difficulty comes from 
the fact that the energy E is concentrated in a very small particle 
while the frequency v, or better the wave length A = c\v, needs for 
definition a (practically) infinite train of waves. 



PHYSICAL REALITY 159 

This paradox can only be solved by sacrificing some traditional 
concept. As we now know, what we have to give up is the idea that 
the particles, considered by themselves, follow deterministic laws 
similar to those of classical mechanics. The theory can predict only 
probabilities, and these are determined by the waves (they are the 
squares of the amplitudes). This is of course a decisive change in our 
attitude to nature. It calls for new ways of describing the physical 
world, but not the denial of its reality. The essence of the new 
method can be seen from a simple example. 

Let a beam of light pass through a Nicol prism; it thus becomes 
linearly polarised. Let this primary beam, which may have the 
amplitude A, pass through a double-refractory crystal; there emerge 
two secondary beams, linearly polarised perpendicularly to one 
another. If is the angle between the direction of polarisation of 
the primary and of one of the secondary beams, the amplitudes of 
the latter are A cos 6 and A sin d. Their intensities are therefore in 
the ratio cos 2 6 : sin 2 6. If now the primary intensity is decreased 
until you see nothing with your eyes, you still can observe the 
arrival of photons with the help of a sensitive photocell and of proper 
amplification, and you can count the number of photons. Thus you 
will find that their average number in the two secondary beams is 
in the ratio of cos 2 6 : sin 2 6. This is the simplest example of the 
statistical interpretation mentioned above, that probabilities are 
determined by the squares of the amplitudes of the waves. The point 
to which I wish to direct attention is that these secondary amplitudes 
are the projections of the primary amplitude in two directions 
determined by the instrument. The prediction made by the theory in 
regard to the intensities of the emerging beams, or the number of 
photons in these, has a meaning only in relation to the whole 
experimental arrangement, the Nicol prism and the crystal. 

Now this example is typical for quantum phenomena. Take for 
example the corresponding experiment with electrons, known as the 
Stern-Gerlach effect, where the Nicol prism is replaced by a non- 
homogeneous magnetic field and the polarization by the direction 
of the spin. Again the observable part, the number of electrons of a 
given spin, depends on the special experimental arrangement in a 
way which can be described by saying that the instrument records 
projections of the actual state. 

This description applies to any quantum effect. An observation or 
measurement does not refer to a natural phenomenon as such, but 
to its aspect from, or its projection on, a system of reference which 
as a matter of fact is the whole apparatus used. Expressed in 
mathematical terms the word projection is perfectly justified since 



l6o PHYSICAL REALITY 

the main operation is a direct generalization of the geometrical act 
of projecting, only in a space of many, often infinitely many, 
dimensions. 

If these facts are analysed from the standpoint of particles alone, 
there appear those uncertainty relations, which I shall not discuss 
here, since they are now to be found in every textbook of quantum 
mechanics. BOHR has introduced the idea of complementarity to 
express the fact that the maximum knowledge of a physical entity 
cannot be obtained from a single observation or a single experimental 
arrangement, but that different experimental arrangements, 
mutually exclusive but complementary, are necessary. In the 
language proposed here this would mean that the maximum know- 
ledge can only be obtained by a sufficient number of independent 
projections of the same physical entity, just as in the case of the 
circular piece of cardboard, where the shadows on several planes 
were necessary to determine its shape and invariant (radius). The 
observations of the different shadows on two perpendicular planes, 
used above to explain the concept of the invariant, also illustrate 
very well the essence of the idea of complementarity. The final 
result of complementary experiments is a set of invariants, charac- 
teristic of the entity. The main invariants are called charge, mass (or 
rather: rest-mass), spin, etc.; and in every instance, when we are 
able to determine these quantities, we decide we have to do with a 
definite particle. I maintain that we are justified in regarding these 
particles as real in a sense not essentially different from the usual 
meaning of the word. 

Before defending this standpoint I wish to discuss in a few words 
the remark often repeated that quantum mechanics has destroyed 
the distinction between object and subject, since it cannot describe 
a situation in nature as such, but only that produced by a man- 
made experiment. This is perfectly true. The atomic physicist is 
very far removed from the idyllic attitude of the old-fashioned 
naturalist who, by watching butterflies in a meadow, hoped to 
penetrate into Nature's mysteries. The observation of atomic 
phenomena needs instruments of such sensitivity that their reaction 
in making measurements must be taken into account, and, as this 
reaction is subject to the same quantum laws as the particles ob- 
served, a degree of uncertainty is introduced, which prohibits 
deterministic prediction. It is therefore obviously futile to ponder 
about the situation which would have arisen without the inter- 
ference of the observer, or independent of the observer. But in 
respect to a given interference of the observer, in a given experi- 
mental situation, quantum mechanics makes definite statements as 



PHYSICAL REALITY l6l 

to the maximum information obtainable. Although we cannot know 
everything, nor even approximate to a knowledge which is complete, 
by improving our instruments we can obtain certain restricted 3 but 
well described, information which is independent of the observer 
and his apparatus, namely the invariant features of a number of 
properly devised experiments. The process of acquiring this informa- 
tion is certainly conditioned by the subject observing; but that does 
not mean that the results lack reality. For obviously the experi- 
mentalist with his apparatus is part of the real world, and even the 
mental processes used in designing his experiment are real. The 
boundary between the action of the subject and the reaction of the 
object is blurred indeed. But this does not prohibit us from using 
these concepts in a reasonable way. The boundary of a liquid and 
its vapour is also blurred, as their atoms are permanently evapora- 
ting and condensing. Still we can speak of liquid and vapour. 

Let us now return to the question of reality and recall the views 
of some modern philosophers on the subject. 

In a recent book the American writer, H. MARGENAU, advocates 
the standpoint that reality consists of two layers: the immediate 
data of the senses, and 'constructs'; the latter include things of 
every day life as well as scientific concepts, as far as they are verifiable 
by several independent experiments. The logical positivists who 
emphatically claim to possess the only rigorous scientific philosophy, 
as far as I understand, regard the constructs merely as conceptual 
tools for surveying and ordering the crude sense data which alone 
have the character of reality. These are minor variations of the 
same theme. These variations appear to me unimportant, as two 
essential points of reality are ignored. One such essential point is 
that it is psychologically and physiologically wrong to regard the 
crude sense impressions as the primary data; the other is that not 
every concept from the domain of scientific constructs has the 
character of a real thing, but only those which are invariant in 
regard to the transformations involved. 

With regard to the first point, we have to remember that every 
human being has already acquired the ability to distinguish and 
recognize objects in his first childhood. As a result, the world of a 
normal human being is not a kaleidoscopic sequence of sensations 
but a comprehensible, continuously changing scene of events in 
which definite things preserve their identity, in spite of their ever 
changing aspects. This power of the mind to neglect the differences 
of sense impressions and to be aware only of their invariant features 
seems to me the most impressive fact of our mental structure. 
Imagine you are walking with your dog beside you. He sees a rabbit 



1 62 PHYSICAL REALITY 

and follows it in a wild chase, and soon the dog will be a tiny spot 
in your field of vision. But all the time you see your dog, not a 
sequence of visual impressions of diminishing size. Modern psychology 
has recognized this fundamental situation; 1 mean the 'Gestalt' 
psychology of KOHLER, HORNBOSTEL, WERTHEIMER, to name only a 
few German psychologists of this school whom I personally knew. 
I should like to translate the word 'Gestalt' not as 'shape' or 'form' 
but as 'invariant', and speak of 'invariants of perception' as the 
elements of our mental world. The physiology and anatomy of the 
nervous system, of which I know a little from the writings of Pro- 
fessor E. D. ADRIAN and Professor J. Z. YOUNG, are in full agreement 
with this result of psychological observation. 

Each single nerve fibre, whether motor or sensor, and in the latter 
case whether carrying tactile, visual, auditory or thermal messages, 
transfers a set of regular pulsations which have not the slightest 
similarity to the physical stimulus. The brain receives nothing but 
sequences of such pulsations, each propagated by a different fibre 
to a definite place in the cortex, and it has the amazing ability to 
disentangle these code messages almost instantaneously. What it 
does is the solution of an extremely difficult problem of algebra, 
determining the invariant features in this welter of ever-changing 
signals. These features thus determine not a blurred set of impressions 
but recognizable things. 

If we attempted to build a philosophy of science on the assump- 
tion that our raw material is unordered sense impressions, we could 
not even describe our manipulations and simple instruments. 
Science must accept, as I said before, the concepts of ordinary life 
and the expressions of ordinary language. It transcends these by 
using magnifying devices, telescopes, microscopes, electro-magnetic 
amplifiers, etc. Thus new situations are encountered where ordinary 
experience breaks down, and we are at a loss how to interpret the 
signals received. You will understand what I mean if you have 
ever looked through a microscope in which a medical friend is 
showing you some remarkable cells or microbes: you see nothing 
but a tangle of vague lines and colours and have to take his word 
for it that some oval yellow structure is the object of interest. 
Exactly the same happens in all branches of physics where amplifica- 
tion is used. We glimpse the unknown, and we are bewildered. For 
we are then not children any more; we have lost the power of 
unconsciously decoding the nerve messages we are receiving, and 
have to use our conscious technique of thinking, mathematics and 
all its tricks (we except a few men of rare genius like FARADAY, 
who saw the inner connection of nature by intuition like a child). 



PHYSICAL REALITY 163 

Thus we apply analysis to construct what is permanent in the flux 
of phenomena, the invariants. Invariants are the concepts of which 
science speaks in the same way as ordinary language speaks of 
'things', and which it provides with names as if they were ordinary 
things. 

Of course, they are not. If we call an electron a particle we know 
very well that it is not exactly like a grain of sand or pollen. For 
instance, it has under certain circumstances not a distinct individu- 
ality: if you shoot an electron out of an atom by another electron, 
you can never tell which of the two electrons flying away is which. 
Still it has some properties in common with ordinary 'particles', 
thus justifying its name. Such extensions of nomenclature are quite 
common in life as in science, and are systematically developed in 
mathematics. A number means originally an integer with which 
you can count a discrete set of objects. But the word is also used for 
fractions like f, radicals like y^2, transcendentals like TT, and 
imaginary numbers like <\/~ i, although you cannot count with 
them. The justification is that they have some formal properties in 
common with integers, each type a little less, but enough to use a 
familiar word for them. The same principle is applied in analytical 
geometry, when we speak of the infinitely distant line in a plane, or 
of a four-dimensional sphere, and so on ; and also in physics. We 
speak of infra-red or ultra-violet light although we cannot see it, 
and of suprasonic sound although we cannot hear it. We are so 
accustomed to extrapolate into regions beyond our sense qualities 
that we have quite forgotten that we are extending concepts beyond 
their original domain of definition. The principle of doing this is 
always the same. Consider the concept of waves. We regard waves 
on a lake as real, though they are nothing material but only a 
certain shape of the surface of the water. The justification is that 
they can be characterized by certain invariant quantities, like 
frequency and wavelength, or a spectrum of these. Now the same 
holds for light waves; why then should we withhold the epithet 
'real 5 , even if the waves represent in quantum theory only a distribu- 
tion of probability ? The feature which suggests reality is always 
some kind of invariance of a structure independent of the aspect, the 
projection. This feature, however, is the same in ordinary life and 
in science, and the continuity between the things of ordinary life and 
the things of science, however remote, compels us to use the same 
language. This is also the condition for preserving the unity of pure 
and applied science. 



IS CLASSICAL MECHANICS IN FACT 
DETERMINISTIC ? 

[First published in Physikalische Blatter, vol. 1 1 (9), 49-54, 1955.] 

THE laws of classical mechanics, and through them the laws of 
classical physics as a whole, are so constructed that, if the 
variables in a closed system are given at some initial point of time, 
they can be calculated for any other instant in principle, at 
least; for it is in most cases beyond human ability to carry out the 
mathematics involved. This deterministic idea has greatly attracted 
many thinkers, and has become an essential part of scientific 
philosophy. Modern physics, however, has been compelled to 
abandon determinism, together with other time-honoured theories 
of space, time and matter, under the pressure of new empirical 
discoveries. Quantum mechanics, which has taken over the place 
of Newtonian mechanics, allows only statistical statements con- 
cerning the behaviour of mass particles. The great majority of 
physicists have become reconciled to this state of affairs, for it 
corresponds exactly to the empirical situation in atomic and nuclear 
physics, where experiments are based fundamentally on the 
counting of events. Among the theoreticians, however, there are 
some who are not content, and they are indeed some of the great 
ones to whom the quantum theory owes its origin and development. 
So far as I know, PLANCK himself was always sceptical towards the 
statistical interpretation of quantum mechanics. The same is true 
of EINSTEIN; even today he continues to point out, by means of 
ingenious examples, contradictions in this interpretation (and he is, 
moreover, still more concerned with the resolution of the concept 
of physical reality, which is closely involved with the problem of 
determinism). SCHRODESTGER goes still further; he proposes to 
abandon the concept of particles (electrons, nuclei, atoms, etc.) 
and to construct the whole of physics upon the idea of waves, which 
obey deterministic laws in accordance with wave mechanics. 
DE BROGLIE (and others) take the opposite course; they reject 
waves, and seek a re-interpretation of quantum mechanics, in which 
everything is in principle determinate, and an uncertainty in 
prediction arises only by the presence.of concealed and unobservable 
parameters. None of these physicists denies that quantum mechanics 
within the realm of its validity (i.e. apart from the theory of 

164 



IS CLASSICAL MECHANICS IN FACT DETERMINISTIC? 165 

elementary particles) is in agreement with experiment and meets all 
the demands of the experimenters. Their rejection is in every case 
founded on the assertion that the usual interpretation of the quantum 
formulae is obscure and philosophically unsatisfactory. 

What now is this philosophy? I do not think it can be traced 
back before GALILEO and NEWTON. There were, of course, predic- 
tions before that in astronomy, of conjunctions and eclipses, but the 
men of antiquity and the Middle Ages saw order and predeter- 
mination only in the celestial spheres, whilst caprice and chaos 
reigned on earth. The religious tenets of fate and predestination 
relate not to the processes of Nature, but to Man, and are certainly 
fundamentally different from the mechanical determinism which 
we here consider. The latter is inconceivable without NEWTON'S 
laws of motion and their astonishing success in the prediction of 
celestial events; it was derived from these laws, and later, during 
the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, became a fundamental 
creed in science as a whole. The remarkable thing here is that the 
undoubted fact that Newtonian mechanics does not suffice to 
account for the observations, particularly in atomic physics, is 
inadequate to shake belief in this abstract theorem. 

But is it certain that classical mechanics in fact permits prediction 
in all circumstances?* My doubts of this increase when I 
compare the time scales of astronomy and atomic physics. The 
age of the universe is reckoned to be some io 9 years, i.e. orbital 
periods of the Earth. The number of periods in the ground state 
of the hydrogen atom, on the other hand, is of the order of io 16 
per second. Thus, when time is measured in the units appropriate 
for each case, the situation is exactly the opposite of the simple 
conception: the stellar universe is short-lived, and the atomic 
universe extremely long-lived. Is it not dangerous to draw, from 
experience of the short-lived universe, conclusions which are to be 
valid for the long-lived one also? 

These doubts are intensified when one considers the kinetic 
theory of gases. It is usually asserted in this theory that the result 
is in principle determinate, and that the introduction of statistical 
considerations is necessitated only by our ignorance of the exact 
initial state of a large number of molecules. I have long thought the 
first part of this assertion to be extremely suspect. Let us consider 
the simple case of a moving spherical molecule, which rebounds 
elastically from numerous other fixed molecules (a kind of three- 
dimensional bagatelle). A very small change in the direction of the 

* The question was raised already by R. v. MISES; s. p. 17, article "On the 
Meaning of Physical Theories", p. 34. 



1 66 IS CLASSICAL MECHANICS IN FACT DETERMINISTIC? 

initial velocity will then result in large changes of the path in the 
zigzag motion; for a small angular change brings about larger and 
larger spatial deviations, and so it must finally happen that a 
sphere which was formerly hit is now missed. If the initial deviation 
in direction is reduced, the moment when the path is changed to 
another is delayed, but it will occur eventually. If we require 
determinacy for all times, the smallest deviation in the initial 
direction must be avoided.* But has this any physical meaning? 
I am convinced that it has not, and that systems of this kind are 
in fact indeterminate. To justify this assertion, a clear compre- 
hension of the idea of determination is needed. 

First of all, we may distinguish between dynamical stability 
and instability. A motion is said to be stable if a small change 
A# , Az> in the initial state (where x denotes the set of all co- 
ordinates and v that of all velocities) causes only a small change 
A#, Az; in the final state (so that, for all times, A* < Mkx , Az; 
< AfA& , where M is a constant of the order of unity) . Otherwise 
the motion is said to be unstable. It is fairly certain that the 
motion of the spheres in the bagatelle game discussed above is 
unstable. (This will be true a fortiori for a gas consisting of many 
moving elastic particles.) The question has been much argued as to 
whether or not the motion of the planets is stable. I do not know 
what is the result of modern research (theory of the three-body 
and many-body problems) ; it is of no importance for our purposes. 
The essential thing is that there are systems which serve as models 
of physical processes, and which, firstly, remain within a finite 
region of space and for which, secondly, all motions are dynamically 
unstable. The gas model which consists of elastic spheres in a 
container with elastic walls is probably such a system, but it is too 
complex to be analysed rigorously. It is sufficient to consider the 
following trivially simple case. A mass particle moves without 
friction along a straight line (the #-axis) under no forces, and is 
elastically reflected at the termini (x = o, x = I). The co-ordinate 
x remains in the finite interval o < x < / for any initial state 
(*o> o)> the velocity v remains constant, but the deviation A* 
increases with time (A* = A# + zAz> ) and takes arbitrarily large 
values at sufficiently remote times. Thus any motion is unstable. 

The connection with the problem of determinism is now evident. 
If we wish to retain the assertion that in this system the initial 
state determines every other state, we are compelled to demand 

* We are evidently dealing with a double limit: the number of collisions tends 
to infinity, while the change in direction tends to zero; the result is undetermined 
in the absence of further data. 



IS CLASSICAL MECHANICS IN FACT DETERMINISTIC? 167 

absolutely exact values of # , v Q9 and to prohibit any deviation 
A# , Az> . We could then speak of 'weak' determinacy, as opposed 
to the 'strong' case where all motions are dynamically stable, and 
therefore predictions are actually possible. This, however, would 
be a mere evasion. The true situation is this. After a critical time 
t c Z/Az> has been reached, the uncertainty A* > Z, and the 
mass point may be found anywhere in the interval o < x < /. 
That is to say, the final position is undetermined. If, however, 
A0 is reduced, the critical time t c is only delayed ; it remains finite 
for any finite A0 , and becomes infinite only for A0 = o, i.e. for an 
absolutely definite initial velocity. 

The connection with the problem of the continuum is evident 
here. An exhaustive discussion of this question would take us too 
far afield, and the following brief remarks must suffice. State- 
ments like C A quantity x has a completely definite value' (expressed 
by a real number and represented by a point in the mathematical 
continuum) seem to me to have no physical meaning. Modern 
physics has achieved its greatest successes by applying a principle 
of methodology, that concepts whose application requires distinc- 
tions that cannot in principle be observed, are meaningless and 
must be eliminated. The most striking examples are EINSTEIN'S 
foundation of the special and general theories of relativity (of which 
the first rejects the concept of absolute simultaneity, and the second 
the distinction between gravity and acceleration as unobservable), 
and HEISENBERG'S foundation of quantum mechanics (by eliminating 
the unobservable orbital radii and frequencies from BOHR'S theory 
of the atom). The problem of continuity calls for the application 
of the same principle. A statement like x = TT cm. would have a 
physical meaning only if one could distinguish between it and 
x = 7T n cm. for every n, where n n is the approximation of n by the 
first n decimals. This, however, is impossible; and even if we 
suppose that the accuracy of measurement will be increased in 
the future, n can always be chosen so large that no experimental 
distinction is possible. 

Of course, I do not intend to banish from physics the idea of a 
real number. It is indispensable for the application of analysis. 
What I mean is that a physical situation must be described by means 
of real numbers in such a way that the natural uncertainty in all 
observations is taken into account. 

Fifty years ago, FELIX KLEIN called for a similar step to be taken 
in geometry. Besides abstract, exact geometry, he desired to have 
a practical geometry, in which a point is replaced by a small spot, 
straight lines by narrow strips, etc. However, nothing much 



1 68 IS CLASSICAL MECHANICS IN FACT DETERMINISTIC? 

resulted from this. In the meantime, physics has independently 
developed the necessary tool, namely physical statistics. The 
statement 'x is equal to a real number' is replaced by c The proba- 
bility that x lies in an interval x < x < x z is P(x l \ x \ # 2 ).' Here 
x, x l3 # 2 , P can be regarded as real numbers, since this is analytically 
convenient, whilst the exact measurability of quantities is not 
involved; P represents only the approximate expectation when 
cases are counted for which x is limited approximately by x 1 and 
x z . In other words, the true physical variable is the probability 
density P(x). 

Quantum mechanics has realized that this is the only possible 
description of physical situations. (However, by introducing 
probability amplitudes, it goes far beyond this statistical view- 
point.) 

In classical mechanics, the statistical method is used only for 
systems of very many individual particles. Our model shows that 
it is obligatory to use it in every case, even that of a single particle 
in the simplest conceivable conditions. This does not require any 
new mathematical considerations; for the law whereby the prob- 
ability density varies is given at once by LIOUVTLLE'S theorem in 
mechanics.* I shall elsewhere discuss exhaustively the mathe- 
matical details and the relation to quantum mechanics. Here I 
shall briefly give some results. 

If we first continue to use classical mechanics, we find that our 
model is perhaps the simplest example of the so-called ergodic 
theorem of statistical mechanics. It can be very easily shown that 
an initial probability density, describing an almost definite state, 
passes in time into what is called the microcanonical distribution. 
This therefore occurs automatically, even for one particle, and has 
nothing to do with the 'large number' of particles. Complex 
systems with energy exchange need be taken into account only if 
we wish to pass to the canonical distribution. 

Now, the same model can also be treated by quantum mechanics. 
An initial state with an uncertainty A# in the initial position is 
then described by a wave packet; the uncertainty Az> in the 
initial velocity cannot be supposed arbitrarily small, but is related 
to A# by HEISENBERG'S uncertainty relation A# . Az> > A/am; 
this holds for all times, the factors A* and Ar> varying with time. If 
both AA: O and A0 can be made small (for large masses), the quantum 
formulae are identical with the classical ones to a close approxi- 
mation, and there is again a critical instant t c where the individual 

* See Appendix. Also Proceedings of the Danish Academy, 30, No. 2, 1955. 
(Festskript til Niels Bohr.) 



IS CLASSICAL MECHANICS IN FACT DETERMINISTIC? 1 69 

motion ceases and a state is entered which can be described only 
statistically. This corresponds exactly to the usual description of a 
motion, in quantum mechanics, by means of stationary waves, 
which is thus the analogue of the classical microcanonical distri- 
bution. 

To summarize, we may say that it is not the introduction of the 
indeterministic statistical description which places quantum mech- 
anics apart from classical mechanics, but other features, above 
all the concept of the probability density as the square of a 
probability amplitude P = | ^ | 2 ; the phenomenon of probability 
interference results from this, and therefore it is impossible to 
apply without modification the idea of an 'object 3 to the mass 
particles of physics : the concept of physical reality must be revised. 
This, however, is beyond the scope of these elementary considera- 
tions. 



APPENDIX 

LIOUVILLE'S theorem expresses the conservation of probability 
density during the motion, and leads to the differential equation 

3P_ 3HBP _ffldP , . 

dt ~~ dx dp dp dsf ' (I) 

where H is HAMILTON'S function. (The expression on the right is 
the so-called Poisson bracket). The solution corresponding to an 
initial state P(x, p, o) = F(x,p} is 

P(*,P* = F Lf(*>P> 0. (*> A *)]> - (*) 

where f(x,p, t) = constant, g(x, p, t) = constant are two integrals 
of the canonical equations of motion, normalized so that 

f(x,p, o) = x, g(x,p, o) = A . . (3) 

The solution of the probability equation (i) and of the canonical 
equations thus present entirely equivalent problems. Nevertheless, 
the solution of (i) furnishes new and interesting results. 

For the example given in the text we have H = P 2 l2m; thus (i) 
becomes 

f - (*=^>- (4> 
Two normalized integrals are^/ = x vt, g = v, and so the solution 

(2) is 

P = F(x vt,v). (5) 

M 



170 IS CLASSICAL MECHANICS IN FACT DETERMINISTIC? 

The boundary conditions amount to the requirement of periodicity 
in #(with period 2/) and antisymmetry in x and v : 

F(x + al,v)=F(x,*),F(-x,-v)=F(x,v). . (6) 
This can be satisfied with an arbitrary function /(#, 0) by 

F(x, ) = S [f( 2 kl + x, v) +f(ati - x, - v)]. . (7) 

k= CO 

If we here replace x by x vt according to (5), we obtain 
P(x,v 9 t). If the position and velocity at the initial instant are 
almost definite, /(#, v) must be taken as a function having a sharp 
maximum at (* , P O ) and vanishingly small elsewhere. If / is a 
Gaussian function in both x (width <T O ) and v (width T O ), the resultant 
^-distribution 

P(x, = f ^(*> *>> * - (8) 

is again a sum of Gaussian functions in x with width 

* 2 ), . . (9) 



which varies as f when t is large. 

This passage to the limit t -^ co can be simply described by draw- 
ing a small circle round the point (x 0) ) in the (x, p) phase space 
(or the #0-plane), and examining how this breaks up into two 
ellipses of equal area with centres # v Q t 9 whose major axes 
become more and more parallel to the #-axis and finally longer 
than the interval /. 



ASTRONOMICAL RECOLLECTIONS 

[First published in Vistas in Astronomy, Vol. i, pp. 41-44, 1955, Pergamon Press, 
London. This work is dedicated to Professor F. J. M. STRATTON for the occasion 
of his seventieth birthday.] 

T AM not an astronomer, nor have I done any work in physics 
* applicable to astronomy. Yet I cannot resist the wish to be 
included amongst those who offer their congratulations to Professor 
STRATTON by an article in this volume. There was a time in my life 
when I was very near to devoting myself to the celestial science; 
but I failed. May I offer, as a substitute for a more serious contribu- 
tion, the story of my wrangling with astronomy and some recollec- 
tions of remarkable astronomers who were my teachers. 

I have to begin with Professor FRANZ, the director of the observa- 
tory of my home city, Breslau. My father, who died just before I 
finished school, had left me the advice to attend lectures on various 
subjects before choosing a definite study for a profession. In Germany 
at that period this was possible because of the complete 'academic 
freedom' at the university. 

There was in most subjects no strict syllabus, no supervision of 
attendance, no examinations except the final ones. Every student 
could select the lectures he liked best; it was his own responsibility 
to build up a body of knowledge sufficient for the final examinations 
which were either for a professional certificate or for a doctor's 
degree, or both. Thus I made up a rather mixed programme for 
my first year, including physics, chemistry, zoology, general philo- 
sophy and logic, mathematics and astronomy. At school I had never 
been very good nor interested in mathematics, but at the university 
the only lectures which I really enjoyed were the mathematical and 
astronomical ones. The greatest disappointment were the philo- 
sophical courses; there we heard a lot about the rules of rational 
thinking, the paradoxes of space, time, substance, cause, the 
structure of the universe, and infinity. Yet it seemed to me an 
awful muddle. Now the same concepts appeared also in the mathe- 
matical and astronomical lectures, but instead of being veiled in a 
mist of paradox they were formulated in a clear way according to 
the case. For that was the important discovery I then made: that 
all the high-sounding words connected with the concept of infinity 
mean nothing unless applied in a definite system of ideas to a 
definite problem. 

171 



172 ASTRONOMICAL RECOLLECTIONS 

Astronomy was attractive in another way. There the problems 
of cosmology are related to the infinity of the physical universe. 
But little about these great questions was mentioned in the elemen- 
tary lectures of our Professor FRANZ. What we had to learn was 
the careful handling of instruments, correct reading of scales, 
elimination of errors of observation and precise numerical calcula- 
tions all the paraphernalia of the measuring scientist. It was a 
rigorous school of precision, and I enjoyed it. It gave one the 
feeling of standing on solid ground. Yet actually this feeling was not 
quite justified by facts. The Breslau observatory was not on solid 
ground, but on the top of the high and steep roof of the lovely 
university building, in a kind of roof pavilion, decorated with 
fantastic baroque ornaments and statues of saints and angels. The 
main instrument was a meridian circle, which a hundred years ago 
had been used by the great BESSEL; although it was placed on a 
solid pillar standing on the foundations and rising straight through 
the whole building, it was not free from vibrations produced by 
the gales blowing from the Polish steppes. The whole outfit of this 
observatory was old-fashioned and more romantic than efficient. 
There were several old telescopes from WALLENSTEIN'S time, like 
those KEPLER may have used. We had no electric chronograph 
but had to learn to observe the stars crossing the threads in the 
field of vision by counting the beats of a big clock and estimating 
the tenths of a second. It was a very good school of observation, and 
it had the additional attraction of an old and romantic craft. 

I remember many an icy winter's night spent there in the little 
roof pavilion. We were only three students in astronomy, and we 
took the observations alternately. When my turn was finished I 
enjoyed looking down on the endless expanse of snow-covered, 
gabled roofs of the ancient city, the silhouettes against the starry 
sky of the massive towers of the churches around the market place 
and of the Cathedral further away beyond the river. There on the 
narrow balcony amongst the stucco saints and old-fashioned 
telescopes, one felt like an adept of Dr. Faustus and would not 
have wondered if Mephistopheles had appeared behind the next 
pillar. However, it was only old Professor FRANZ who came up the 
steps to look after his three students he had not had so many for 
a long time and who carried with him the soberness of the exact 
scientist, checking our results and criticizing our endeavours with 
mild and friendly irony. 

These, our results, I rather think were not very reliable; it was 
not so much our fault as that of the exalted but exposed position 
of the observatory. Professor FRANZ himself, therefore, abstained 



ASTRONOMICAL RECOLLECTIONS 1 73 

from doing research, which needed exact measurements, and 
restricted himself to descriptive work, a thorough study of the 
moon's surface which he knew better than the geography of our 
own planet He made strenuous efforts, however, to obtain a 
modern observatory but never succeeded. During my student time 
there were great hopes. The firm Carl Zeiss, Jena, had sent a set of 
modern instruments to the World's Fair at Chicago. After the end 
of the show these were purchased by the Prussian State for its 
university observatories. Breslau obtained an excellent meridian 
instrument and a big parallactic telescope; yet no proper building 
was granted, and the meridian circle was installed in a wooden 
cabin on a narrow island of the Oder River, just opposite the 
university building. This island was in fact an artificial dam between 
the river and a lock through which many barges used to pass. The 
time service for the province of Silesia, which had been practised 
for scores of years with the help of the old BESSEL circle, was trans- 
ferred to the new Zeiss instruments, but the results remained highly 
unsatisfactory. Eventually we discovered a correlation between the 
strange irregularities of the time observations with the changing 
level of the water in the lock; the island suffered small displacements 
through the water pressure. Professor FRANZ'S hopes of a more 
efficient observatory had broken down again. 

We youngsters took this disappointment rather as a funny inci- 
dent. It did not diminish the fascination which astronomy exerted 
on my mind. This fascination was, however, shattered by the 
horrors of computation. FRANZ gave us a lecture on the determina- 
tion of planetary orbits, connected with a practical course where 
we had to learn the technique of computing, filling in endless 
columns of seven decimal logarithms of trigonometric functions 
according to traditional forms. I knew from school that I was 
bad at numerical work, but I tried hard to improve. It was in 
vain, there was always a mistake somewhere in my figures, and my 
results differed from those of the class mates. I was teased by them, 
but that made it worse. I do not think that I ever finished an orbit 
or an ephemeris, and then I gave up not only this calculating 
business but the whole idea of becoming an astronomer. If I had 
known at that time that there was in existence another kind of 
astronomy which did not consider the prediction of planetary 
positions as the ultimate aim, but studied the physical structure of 
the universe with all the powerful instruments and concepts of 
modern physics, my decision might have been different. But I 
came in contact with astrophysics only some years later, when it 
was too late to change my plans. 



174 ASTRONOMICAL RECOLLECTIONS 

At that period German students used to move from one university 
to another, from different motives. Sometimes they were attracted 
by a celebrated professor or a well-equipped laboratory, in other 
cases by the amenities and beauties of a city, by its museums, 
concerts, theatres, or by winter sport, by carnival and gay life in 
general. Thus I spent two summer semesters in Heidelberg and 
Zurich, returning during the winter to the home university. The 
observatory of Heidelberg was on the Konigstuhl, a considerable, 
wooded hill, where the astronomers lived a secluded life remote 
from the ordinary crowd. I had then definitely changed over to 
physics, and not even the celebrated name of WOLF, the professor 
who has discovered more planetoids than anybody else, deflected 
me from my purpose. 

The observatory in Zurich was more accessible, and the name of 
the professor was WOLFER, which could be interpreted as a com- 
parative to WOLF. But even that did not attract me. 

The following summer I went to Gottingen for the rest of my 
student time. There KARL SCHWARZSCHILD was director of the 
famous observatory which had been for many years under the 
great GAUSS. SGHWARZSCHILD was the youngest professor of the 
university, about thirty years of age; a small man with dark hair 
and a moustache, sparkling eyes and an unforgettable smile. I 
joined his astrophysical seminar and was for the first time intro- 
duced to the modern aspect of astronomy. We discussed the atmos- 
phere of planets, and I had to give an account of the loss of gas 
through diffusion against gravity into interstellar space. Thus I 
was driven to a careful study of the kinetic theory of gases which 
then, in 1904, was not a regular part of the syllabus in physics. 
But this is not the only subject which I first learned through 
SGHWARZSGHILD'S teaching. His was a versatile, all-embracing mind, 
and astronomy proper only one field of many in which he was 
interested. About this time he published deep investigations on 
electro-dynamics, in particular on the variational principle from 
which LORENTZ'S equations for the field of an electron and for its 
motion could be derived. In the following year (1905) there ap- 
peared the first of his great articles on the aberrations of optical 
instruments; these are, in my opinion, classical investigations, unsur- 
passed in clarity and rigour by later work. I have presented this 
method in my book Optik (Springer, 1932), and it is again to be 
the backbone of a modernized version which will appear soon as 
an English book on optics (in collaboration with E. WOLF*). 

* Pergamon Press, London. To be published. 



ASTRONOMICAL RECOLLECTIONS 175 

SCHWARZSGHILD applied his aberration formulae to the actual 
construction of new types of optical systems; but I am not com- 
petent to speak about this part of his activities. Nor can I discuss 
his astronomical work, experimental or theoretical. Personally he 
was a most charming man, always cheerful, amusing, slightly 
sarcastic, but kind and helpful. He once saved me from an awkward 
situation. I had intended to take geometry as one of my subjects in 
the oral examinations for the doctor's degree, but was not attracted 
by the lectures of FELIX KLEIN, the famous mathematician, and 
attended somewhat irregularly. This fact did not escape KLEIN'S 
observation and he showed me his displeasure. A disaster at the 
orals, only six months ahead, seemed to be impending. But 
SCHWARZSGHILD said that half a year was ample time to learn the 
whole of astronomy. He gave me some books to read and tutored 
me a little, in exchange for my training him in tennis. When the 
examination came his first question was: What do you do when 
you see a falling star?' Whereupon I answered at once: C I make a 
wish' according to an old German superstition that such a wish 
is always fulfilled. He remained quite serious and continued: 
'Yes, and what do you do then?' Whereupon I gave the expected 
answer: e l would look at my watch, remember the time, constella- 
tion of appearance, direction of motion, range, etc., go home and 
work out a crude orbit'. Which led to celestial mechanics and to a 
satisfactory pass. SCHWARZSGHILD differed from the ordinary type 
of the dignified, bearded German scholar of that time; not only in 
appearance, but also in his mental structure, which was thoroughly 
modern, cheerful, active, open to all problems of the day. Still he 
had his hours of professorial absent-mindedness. There was a 
'Stammtisch', a certain table in a restaurant where a group of 
young professors and lecturers used to meet for lunch. SCHWARZ- 
SGHILD was one of them until his marriage. A few weeks after the 
wedding he was again at his accustomed place at the lunch table 
and plunged in his usual way into a lively discussion about some 
scientific problem, until one of the men asked him: 'Now, SCHWARZ- 
SCHILD, how do you like married life?' He blushed, jumped up, said: 
* Married life oh, I have quite forgotten ', got his hat and ran 
away. But I think this kind of behaviour was not typical of him. 
He always knew what he was doing. His life was short, his achieve- 
ments amazing, his success great his end tragic. When the great 
war of 1914-18 broke out he was employed as a mathematical 
expert in ballistics and attached to the staff of one of the armies 
on the Eastern front. There, in Russia, he contracted some rare 
infectious disease. It was said that he refused to be sent home, until 



176 ASTRONOMICAL RECOLLECTIONS 

it was too late. On his way home, he visited me in my military 
office in Berlin; he was still cheerful, but he looked terribly ill. 
Soon after he died. Now his son, Martin, keeps up the astronomical 
tradition, thus founding another one of those hereditary lines of 
astronomers, the HERSGHELS, the STRUVES, and so on, 

I have met many other distinguished astronomers and been 
intimate with some of them; but as most of them are still wandering 
on this globe, I had better refrain from telling stories about them. 

May I conclude by wishing Professor STRATTON many happy 
returns and by adding the request that he too may present us with 
some recollections of astronomical personalities out of his long 
experience. 



STATISTICAL INTERPRETATION OF 
QUANTUM MECHANICS 

[First published in Science, Vol. 122, No. 3172, pp. 675-679 (1955). This 
article is the English translation of the lecture Professor BORN gave in German 
when he was awarded the Nobel Prize for Physics in 1954, a prize which he 
shared with W. BOTHE.] 

'""pHE published work for which the honour of the Nobel prize 
-*- for the year 1954 has been accorded to me does not contain 
the discovery of a new phenomenon of nature but, rather, the 
foundations of a new way of thinking about the phenomena of 
nature. This way of thinking has permeated experimental and 
theoretical physics to such an extent that it seems scarcely possible 
to say anything more about it that has not often been said already. 
Yet there are some special aspects that I should like to discuss. 

The first point is this : The work of the Gottingen school, of which 
I was at that time the director, during the years 1926 and 1927, 
contributed to the solution of an intellectual crisis into which our 
science had fallen through PLANCK'S discovery of the quantum of 
action in the year 1900. To-day physics is in a similar crisis I do 
not refer to its implication in politics and economics consequent on 
the mastery of a new and terrible force of nature, but I am thinking 
of the logical and epistemological problems posed by nuclear physics. 
Perhaps it is a good thing to remind oneself at such a time of what 
happened earlier in a similar situation, especially since these events 
are not without a certain element of drama. In the second place, 
when I say that physicists had accepted the way of thinking deve- 
loped by us at that time, I am not quite correct. There are a few 
most noteworthy exceptions namely, among those very workers 
who have contributed most to the building up of quantum theory. 
PLANCK himself belonged to the sceptics until his death. EINSTEIN, 
DE BROGLIE, and SCHRODINGER have not ceased to emphasize the 
unsatisfactory features of quantum mechanics, and to demand a 
return to the concepts of classical, Newtonian physics, and to 
propose ways in which this could be done without contradicting 
experimental facts. One cannot leave such weighty views unheard. 
NIELS BOHR has gone to much trouble to refute the objections. I 
have myself pondered on them and believe I can contribute some- 
thing to the clarification of the situation. We are concerned with 
the borderland between physics and philosophy, and so my physical 



178 STATISTICAL INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 

lecture will be partly historically and partly philosophically coloured, 
for which I ask indulgence. 

First of all, let me relate how quantum mechanics and its 
statistical interpretation arose. At the beginning of the 1 920*3 
every physicist, I imagine, was convinced that PLANCK'S hypothesis 
was correct, according to which the energy in oscillations of definite 
frequency v (for example, in light waves) occurs in finite quanta 
of size hv. Innumerable experiments could be explained in this 
manner and always gave the same value of PLANCK'S constant h. 
Furthermore, EINSTEIN'S assertion that light quanta carry momen- 
tum hv\c (where c is the velocity of light) was well supported by 
experiment. This meant a new lease of life for the corpuscular 
theory of light for a certain complex of phenomena. For other 
processes, the wave theory was appropriate. Physicists accustomed 
themselves to this duality and learned to handle it to a certain 
extent. 

In 1913 NIELS BOHR had solved the riddle of line spectra by using 
quantum theory and at the same time had explained, in their 
main features, the wonderful stability of atoms, the structure of 
their electronic shells, and the periodic system of the elements. 
For the sequel the most important assumption of his teaching was 
this: an atomic system cannot exist in all mechanically possible 
states, which form a continuum, but in a series of discrete 'stationary' 
states; in a transition from one to another the difference in energy 
E m E n is emitted or absorbed as a light quantum hv mn (according 
as E m is greater or less than JE n ). This is an interpretation, in 
terms of energy, of the fundamental law of spectroscop'y discovered 
some years previously by W. Rrrz. The situation can be pictured 
by writing the energy levels of the stationary states twice over, 
horizontally and vertically; a rectangular array results 



II 12 13 

21 22 23 



in which positions on the diagonal correspond to the states and off- 
diagonal positions correspond to the transitions. 

BOHR was fully aware that the law thus formulated is in conflict 
with mechanics and that, therefore, even the use of the concept of 
energy in this context is problematical. He based this bold fusion 
of the old with the new on his principle of correspondence. This 



STATISTICAL INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 179 

consists in the obvious requirement that ordinary classical mech- 
anics must hold to a high degree of approximation in the limit, 
when the numbers attached to the stationary states, the quantum 
numbers, are very large that is, far to the right and low down in 
the foregoing array so that the energy changes relatively little 
from place to place that is, practically continuously. 

Theoretical physics lived on this idea for the next 10 years. 
The problem was that a harmonic oscillator possesses not only 
frequency but intensity as well. For each transition in the scheme 
there must be a corresponding intensity. How is the latter to be 
found by considerations of correspondence ? It was a question of 
guessing the unknown from a knowledge of a limiting case. Con- 
siderable success was achieved by BOHR himself, by KRAMERS, by 
SOMMERFELD, by EPSTEIN, and by many others. But the decisive 
step was again taken by EINSTEIN, who, by a new derivation of 
PLANCK'S radiation formula, made it evident that the classical con- 
cept of intensity of emission must be replaced by the statistical idea 
of transition probability. To each position in our scheme there 
belongs, besides the frequency v mn = (E m W )/A, a certain 
probability for the transition accompanied by emission or absorption 
of radiation. 

In Gottingen we also took part in the attempts to distill the 
unknown mechanics of the atom out of the experimental results. 
The logical difficulty became ever more acute. Investigations on 
scattering and dispersion of light showed that EINSTEIN'S conception 
of transition probability as a measure of the strength of an oscillation 
was not adequate, and the idea of an oscillation amplitude asso- 
ciated with each transition could not be dispensed with. In this 
connection work by LADENBURG [i], KRAMERS [2], HEISENBERG [3], 
JORDAN and I [4] may be mentioned. The art of guessing correct 
formulas, which depart from the classical formulas but pass over 
into them in the sense of the correspondence principle, was brought 
to considerable perfection. A paper of mine, which introduced in 
its title the expression 'quantum mechanics', probably for the first 
time, contains a very involved formula still valid at the present 
time for the mutual disturbance of atomic systems. 

This period was brought to a sudden end by HEISENBERG [5], 
who was my assistant at that time. He cut the Gordian knot by a 
philosophical principle and replaced guesswork by a mathematical 
rule. The principle asserts that concepts and pictures that do not 
correspond to physically observable facts should not be used in 
theoretical description. When EINSTEIN, in setting up his theory of 
relativity, eliminated the concepts of the absolute velocity of a 



l8o STATISTICAL INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 

body and of the absolute simultaneity of two events at different 
places, he was making use of the same principle. HEISENBERG 
banished the picture of electron orbits with definite radii and periods 
of rotation, because these quantities are not observable; he 
demanded that the theory should be built up by means of quadratic 
arrays of the kind suggested in a preceding paragraph. Instead of 
describing the motion by giving a co-ordinate as a function of time 
x(i), one ought to determine an array of transition probabilities 
x mn . To me the decisive part in his work is the requirement that one 
must find a rule whereby from a given array 



the array for the square, 
(* 2 )u 



may be found (or, in general, the multiplication law of such arrays). 

By consideration of known examples discovered by guesswork he 
found this rule and applied it with success to simple examples such 
as the harmonic and anharmonic oscillator. This was in the summer 
of 1925. HEISENBERG, suffering from a severe attack of hay fever, 
took leave of absence for a course of treatment at the seaside and 
handed over his paper to me for publication, if I thought I could 
do anything about it. 

The significance of the idea was immediately clear to me, and I 
sent the manuscript to the %eitschrift fur Physik. HEISENBERG'S rule 
of multiplication left me no peace, and after a week of intensive 
thought and trial, I suddenly remembered an algebraic theory that 
I had learned from my teacher, ROSANES, in Breslau. Such quadratic 
arrays are quite familiar to mathematicians and are called matrices, 
in association with a definite rule of multiplication. I applied this 
rule to HEISENBERG'S quantum condition and found that it agreed 
for the diagonal elements. It was easy to guess what the remaining 
elements must be, namely, null; and immediately there stood before 
me the strange formula 

pq qp A/2?n. 



STATISTICAL INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS l8l 

This meant that co-ordinates q and momenta p are not to be repre- 
sented by the values of numbers but by symbols whose product 
depends on the order of multiplication which do not 'commute 9 , 
as we say. 

My excitement over this result was like that of the mariner who, 
after long voyaging, sees the desired land from afar, and my only 
regret was that HEISENBERG was not with me. I was convinced 
from the first that we had stumbled on the truth. Yet again a large 
part was only guesswork, in particular the vanishing of the non- 
diagonal elements in the foregoing expression. For this problem I 
secured the collaboration of my pupil PASCUAL JORDAN, and in a 
few days we succeeded in showing that I had guessed correctly. 
The joint paper by JORDAN and myself [6] contains the most 
important principles of quantum mechanics, including its extension 
to electrodynamics. 

There followed a hectic period of collaboration among the three 
of us, rendered difficult by HEISENBERG'S absence. There was a 
lively interchange of letters, my contribution to which unfortunately 
went amiss in the political disorders. The result was a three-man 
paper [7], which brought the formal side of the investigation to a 
certain degree of completeness. Before this paper appeared, the 
first dramatic surprise occurred: PAUL DIRAC'S paper [8] on the 
same subject. The stimulus received through a lecture by HEISEN- 
BERG in Cambridge led him to results similar to ours in Gottingen, 
with the difference that he did not have recourse to the known matrix 
theory of the mathematicians but discovered for himself and elab- 
orated the doctrine of such non-commuting symbols. 

The first non-trivial and physically important application of 
quantum mechanics was made soon afterwards by W. PAULI [9], 
who calculated the stationary energy values of the hydrogen atom 
by the matrix method and found complete agreement with BOHR'S 
formulas. From this moment there was no longer any doubt about 
the correctness of the theory. 

What the real significance of this formalism might be was, how- 
ever, by no means clear. Mathematics, as often happens, was 
wiser than interpretative thought. While we were still discussing 
the point, there occurred the second dramatic surprise: the appear- 
ance of SCHRODINGER'S celebrated papers [10]. He followed quite 
a different line of thought, which derived from Louis DE BROGLIE 
[i i]. The latter had a few years previously made the bold assertion, 
supported by brilliant theoretical considerations, that wave- 
corpuscle dualism, familiar to physicists in the case of light, must 
also be exhibited by electrons; to each freely movable electron 



1 82 STATISTICAL INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 

there belongs, according to these ideas, a plane wave of perfectly 
definite wavelength, determined by PLANCK'S constant and the mass. 
This exciting essay by DE BROGLIE was well known to us in Got- 
tingen. 

One day in 1925 I received a letter from C. J. DAVISSON con- 
taining singular results on the reflection of electrons from metallic 
surfaces. My colleague on the experimental side, JAMES FRANCK, 
and I at once conjectured that these curves of DAVISSON'S were 
crystal-lattice spectra of DE BROGLIE'S electron waves, and we 
arranged for one of our pupils, W. ELSASSER [12], to investigate 
the matter. His result provided the first quantitative proof of DE 
BROGLIE'S idea, a proof independently given later by DAVISSON and 
GERMER [13] and by G. P. THOMSON [14], by systematic experi- 
ments. 

But this familiarity with DE BROGLIE'S line of thought did not 
lead on further toward an application to the electronic structure of 
atoms. This was reserved for SCHRODINGER. He extended DE 
BROGLIE'S wave equation, which applied to free motion, to the 
case in which forces act and gave an exact formulation of the 
additional conditions, already hinted at by DE BROGLIE, to which the 
wave function ijr must be subjected namely, that it should be 
single-valued and finite in space and time and he succeeded in 
deriving the stationary states of the hydrogen atom as mono- 
chromatic solutions of his wave equation not extending to infinity. 
For a short while, at the beginning of 1926, it looked as if suddenly 
there were two self-contained but entirely distinct systems of ex- 
planation in the field matrix mechanics and wave mechanics. 
But SCHRODINGER himself soon demonstrated their complete 
equivalence. 

Wave mechanics enjoyed much greater popularity than the 
Gottingen or Cambridge version of quantum mechanics. Wave 
mechanics operates with a wave function ^, which at least in 
the case of one particle can be pictured in space, and it employs 
the mathematical methods of partial differential equations familiar 
to every physicist. SCHRODINGER also believed that his wave theory 
made possible a return to deterministic classical physics; he pro- 
posed (and has emphatically renewed this suggestion quite recently, 
[i 5]) to abandon the particle picture entirely and to speak of electrons 
not as particles but as a continuous ^density distribution |^| 2 , 
or electric density e\ i/r | 2 . 

To us in Gottingen this interpretation appeared unacceptable in 
the face of the experimental facts. At that time it was already possible 
to count particles by means of scintillations or with the Geiger 



STATISTICAL INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 183 

counter and to photograph their tracks with the help of the Wilson 
cloud chamber. 

It appeared to me that it was not possible to arrive at a clear 
interpretation of the ^-function by considering bound electrons. I 
had therefore been at pains, as early as the end of 1925, to extend 
the matrix method, which obviously covered only oscillatory pro- 
cesses, in such a way as to be applicable to aperiodic processes. I 
was at that time the guest of the Massachusetts Institute of Tech- 
nology in the U.S.A., and there I found in NORBERT WIENER a 
distinguished collaborator. In our joint paper [16] we replaced the 
matrix by the general concept of an operator and, in this way, 
made possible the description of aperiodic processes. Yet we missed 
the true approach, which was reserved for SGHRODINGER; and I 
immediately took up his method, since it promised to lead to an 
interpretation of the ^-function. Once more an idea of EINSTEIN'S 
gave the lead. He had sought to make the duality of particles (light 
quanta or photons) and waves comprehensible by interpreting the 
square of the optical wave amplitudes as probability density for the 
occurrence of photons. This idea could at once be extended to the 
^-function: \i/r\ 2 must represent the probability density for 
electrons (or other particles). To assert this was easy; but how was 
it to be proved? 

For this purpose atomic scattering processes suggested themselves. 
A shower of electrons coming from an infinite distance, represented 
by an incident wave of known intensity (that is, |^| 2 ) impinge 
on an obstacle, say a heavy atom. In the same way that the water 
wave caused by a steamer excites secondary circular waves in 
striking a pile, the incident electron wave is partly transformed by 
the atom into a secondary spherical wave, whose amplitude of 
oscillation ft is different in different directions. The square of the 
amplitude of this wave at a great distance from the scattering centre 
then determines the relative probability of scattering in its depend- 
ence on direction. If, in addition, the scattering atom is itself 
capable of existing in different stationary states, one also obtains 
quite automatically from SCHRODINGER'S wave equation the pro- 
babilities of excitation of these states, the electron being scattered 
with loss of energy, or inelastically, as it is termed. In this way it 
was possible to give the assumptions of BOHR'S theory, first verified 
experimentally by FRANCK and HERTZ, a theoretical basis [17]. 
Soon WENTZEL [18] succeeded in deriving RUTHERFORD'S celebrated 
formula for the scattering of a-particles from my theory. 

But the factor that contributed more than these successes to the 
speedy acceptance of the statistical interpretation of the ^-function 



184 STATISTICAL INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 

was a paper by HEISENBERG [19] that contained his celebrated 
uncertainty relationship, through which the revolutionary character 
of the new conception was first made clear. It appeared that it was 
necessary to abandon not only classical physics but also the naive 
conception of reality that thought of the particles of atomic physics 
as if they were exceedingly small grains of sand. A grain of sand 
has at each instant a definite position and velocity. For an electron 
this is not the case; if one determines the position with increasing 
accuracy, the possibility of determining the velocity becomes less, 
and vice versa. I shall return to these questions in a more general 
connection, but before doing so would like to say a few words about 
the theory of collisions. 

The mathematical techniques of approximation I used were 
somewhat primitive and were soon improved. Out of the literature, 
which has grown to unmanageable proportions, I can name only 
a few of the earliest authors, to whom the theory is indebted for 
considerable progress: HOLTSMARK in Norway, FAXEN in Sweden, 
BETHE in Germany, MOTT and MASSEY in Great Britain. 

To-day collision theory is a special science, with its own volumin- 
ous text-books, and has grown completely over my head. Of course, 
in the last resort all the modern branches of physics, quantum 
electrodynamics, the theory of mesons, nuclei, cosmic rays, ele- 
mentary particles and their transformations, all belong to this 
range of ideas, to a discussion of which no bounds could be set. 

I should also like to state that during the years 1926 and 1927 
I tried another way of justifying the statistical conception of quan- 
tum mechanics, partly in collaboration with the Russian physicist 
FOCK [20]. In the afore-mentioned three-man paper there is a 
chapter in which the SCHRODINGER function is really anticipated; 
only it is not thought of as a function ft of space, but as function ft n 
of the discrete index n = i, 2, ... which enumerates the 
stationary states. If the system under consideration is subject to a 
force that is variable in time, i/r n also becomes time-dependent, and 
| ft n (t) \ 2 denotes the probability for the existence of that state 
n at time t. 

Starting from an initial distribution in which only one state is 
present, we obtain in this manner transition probabilities, and we 
can investigate their properties. In particular, what interested me 
most at the time was what happens in the adiabatic limiting case, 
that is, in the case of very slowly variable external action; it was 
possible to show that, as might have been expected, the probability 
of transitions became ever smaller. The theory of transition 
probabilities was developed independently by DIRAG and made to 



STATISTICAL INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 185 

yield results. It may be said that the whole of atomic and nuclear 
physics works with this system of concepts, especially in the extremely 
elegant form given to them by DIRAC [21] ; almost all experiments 
lead to statements about relative probabilities of events, even if they 
appear concealed under the name cross section or the like. 

How then does it come about that great discoverers such as 
EINSTEIN, SCHRODINGER, and DE BROGUE are not satisfied with the 
situation? As a matter of fact, all these objections are directed not 
against the correctness of the formulas but against their inter- 
pretation. Two closely interwoven points of view must be distin- 
guished : the question of determinism and the question of reality. 

Newtonian mechanics is deterministic in the following sense. If 
the initial state (positions and velocities of all particles) of a system 
is accurately given, the state at any other tune (earlier or later) 
may be calculated from the laws of mechanics. All the other 
branches of classical physics have been built up in accordance with 
this pattern. Mechanical determinism gradually became an article 
of faith the universe as a machine, an automaton. As far as I 
can see, this idea has no precursors in ancient or mediaeval phil- 
osophy; it is a product of the immense success of Newtonian 
mechanics, especially in astronomy. In the nineteenth century it 
became a fundamental philosophic principle for the whole of exact 
science. I asked myself whether this was really justified. Can we 
really make absolute predictions for all time on the basis of the 
classical equations of motion? It is easily seen, by simple examples, 
that this is the case only if we assume the possibility of absolutely 
accurate measurement (of the position, velocity, or other quantities). 
Let us consider a particle moving without friction on a straight line 
between two end-points (walls) at which it suffers perfectly elastic 
recoil. The particle moves backward and forward with constant 
speed equal to its initial speed z> , and one can say exactly where it 
will be at a stated time provided that V Q is accurately known. 

But if we allow a small inaccuracy Az> , the inaccuracy of the 
prediction of position at time t is fAz; ; that is, it increases with t. 
If we wait long enough, until time t c = Z/ Az> , where c is the dis- 
tance between the elastic walls, the inaccuracy A* will have become 
equal to the whole interval L Thus it is possible to say absolutely 
nothing about the position at a time later than t c . Determinism 
becomes complete indeterminism if one admits even the smallest 
inaccuracy in the velocity datum. Is there any sense I mean 
physical, not metaphysical, sense in which one can speak of abso- 
lute data? Is it justifiable to say that the co-ordinate x is TT cm, 
where TT = 3-1415 .- is the familiar transcendental number 

N 



1 86 STATISTICAL INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 

that determines the ratio of the circumference of a circle to its 
diameter? As an instrument of mathematics, the concept of a 
real number represented by a nonterminating decimal is extremely 
important and fruitful. As a measure of a physical quantity, the 
concept is nonsensical. If the decimal for TT is interrupted at the 
soth or 25th place, two numbers are obtained which cannot be 
distinguished by any measurement from each other and from the 
true value. According to the heuristic principle employed by 
EINSTEIN in the theory of relativity and by HEISENBERG in quantum 
theory, concepts that correspond to no conceivable observation 
ought to be eliminated from physics. This is possible without 
difficulty in the present case also; we have only to replace state- 
ments like x = TT cm. by: the probability of the distribution of 
values of # has a sharp maximum at x == TT cm.; and (if we wish to 
be more accurate) we can add : of such and such a breadth. In 
short, ordinary mechanics must be formulated statistically. I have 
occupied myself with this formulation a little recently and have 
seen that it is possible without difficulty. This is not the place to go 
into the matter more closely. I only wish to emphasize the point 
that the determinism of classical physics turns out to be a false 
appearance, produced by ascribing too much weight to mathe- 
maticological conceptual structures. It is an idol, not an ideal, in 
the investigation of nature and, therefore, cannot be used as an 
objection to the essentially indeterministic, statistical interpretation 
of quantum mechanics. 

Much more difficult is the objection concerned with reality. The 
concept of a particle, for example, a grain of sand, contains impli- 
citly the notion that it is at a definite position and has a definite 
motion. But according to quantum mechanics it is impossible to 
determine simultaneously with arbitrary accuracy position and 
motion (more correctly momentum, that is, mass times velocity). 
Thus two questions arise. First, what is there to prevent us from 
measuring both quantities with arbitrary accuracy by refined 
experiments, in spite of the theoretical assertion? Second, if it 
should really turn out that this is not feasible, are we still justified 
in applying to the electron the concept of particle and the ideas 
associated with it? 

With regard to the first question, it is clear that if the theory is 
correct and we have sufficient grounds for believing this the 
obstacle to simultaneous measurability of position and motion (and 
of other similar pairs of so-called 'conjugate' quantities) must lie 
in the laws of quantum mechanics itself. This is indeed the case, 
but it is not at all obvious. NIELS BOHR himself has devoted much 



STATISTICAL INTERPRETATION OF QUANTUM MECHANICS 187 

labour and ingenuity to developing a theory of measurements to 
clear up this situation and to meet the most subtle considerations 
of EINSTEIN, who repeatedly tried to think out measuring devices 
by means of which position and motion could be measured simul- 
taneously and exactly. The conclusion is as follows. In order to 
measure space co-ordinates and instants of time rigid measuring 
rods and clocks are required. On the other hand to measure 
momenta and energies arrangements with movable parts are 
needed to take up and indicate the impact of the object to be 
measured. If we take into consideration the fact that quantum 
mechanics is appropriate for dealing with the interaction of object 
and apparatus, we see that no arrangement is possible that satisfies 
both conditions at the same time. There exist, therefore, mutually 
exclusive but complementary experiments, which only in combina- 
tion with each other disclose all that can be learned about an 
object. This idea of complementarity in physics is generally regarded 
as the key to the intuitive understanding of quantum processes. 
BOHR has transferred the idea in an ingenious manner to completely 
different fields for example, to the relationship between conscious- 
ness and brain, to the problem of free will, and to other fundamental 
problems of philosophy. 

Now to come to the final point can we still call something with 
which the concepts of position and motion cannot be associated in 
the usual way a thing, a particle? And if not, what is the reality that 
our theory has been invented to describe? 

The answer to this question is no longer physics, but philosophy, 
and to deal with it completely would overstep the bounds of this 
lecture. I have expounded my views on it fully elsewhere [23]. 
Here I will only say that I am emphatically for the retention of the 
particle idea. Naturally it is necessary to redefine what is meant. 
For this purpose well-developed concepts are available, which are 
familiar in mathematics under the name of invariants with respect 
to transformations. Every object that we perceive appears in 
innumerable aspects. The concept of the object is the invariant 
of all these aspects. From this point of view, the present universally 
used conceptual system, in which particles and waves occur at the 
same time, can be completely justified. 

The most recent research on nuclei and elementary particles has, 
however, led us to limits beyond which this conceptual system in its 
turn does not appear to suffice. The lesson to be learned from the 
story I have told of the origin of quantum mechanics is that, pre- 
sumably, a refinement of mathematical methods will not suffice to 
produce a satisfactory theory, but that somewhere in our doctrine 



1 88 STATISTICAL INTERPRETAHONJDF QUANTUM MECHANICS 

there lurks a concept not justified by any experience, which will 
have to be eliminated in order to clear the way. 

REFERENCES 

1. R. LADENBURG, . Physik 4, 451 (1921); R. LADENBURG and F. REICHE, 

Naturwiss. 11, 584 (1923). 

2. H. A. KRAMERS, Nature 113, 673 (1924). 

3. and W. HEISENBERG, . Physik 31, 631 (1925). 

4. M. BORN, ibid. 26, 379 (1924) ; M. BORN and P. JORDAN, ibid. 33, 479 (1925). 

5. W. HEISENBERG, ibid. 33, 879 (1925). 

6. M. BORN and P. JORDAN, ibid. 34, 358 (1925). 

7. M. BORN, W. HEISENBERG, P. JORDAN, ibid. 35, 557 (1926). 

8. P. A. M. DIRAC, Proc. Roy. Soc. (London] AHM), 643 (1925). 

9. W. PAUIJ, Z- Physik 36, 336 (1926). 

10. E. ScHRdDiNGER, Ann. Physik (4), 79, 361, 489, 734 (1926); 80, 437 (1926); 

81, 109 (1926). 
n. Louis DE BROGLIE, Theses, Paris, 1924; Ann. Physik (10), 3, 22 (1925). 

12. W. ELSASSER, Naturwiss. 13, 711 (1925). 

13. C. J. DAVISSON and L. H. GERMER, Phys. Rev. 30, 707 (1927). 

14. G. P. THOMSON and A. RJEID, Nature 119, 890 (1927); G. P. THOMSON, Proc. 

Roy Soc. (London) Aii7, 600 (1928). 

15. E. SCHRODINGER, Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 3, 109, 233 (1952). 

1 6. M. BORN and N. WIENER, . Physik 36, 174 (1926). 

17. M. BORN, ibid. 37, 863 (1926); 38, 803 (1926); Gott. Nachr. Math.-Physik 

Ki, i, 146 (1926). 

1 8. G. WENTZEL, . Physik 40, 590 (1926). 



19. W. HEISENBERG, ibid. 43, 172 (1927). 

20. M. BORN, ibid. 40, 167 (1926); M. BORN and V. FOGK, ibid., 51, 165 (1928). 

21. P. A. M. DIRAG, Proc. Roy. Soc. (London) Aiog, 642 (1925); no, 561 (1926); 



in, 281 (1926); 112, 674 (1926). 

22. NIELS BOHR, Naturwiss. 16, 245 (1928); 17, 483 (1929); ai, 13 (1933); 

'Causality and complementarity', Die Erkemtnis 6, 293 (1936). 

23. M. BORN, Phil. Quart. 3, 134 (1953); Physik. Bl. 10, 49 (1954). 



PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 

[A lecture given at the International Relativity Conference in Berne, Switzerland, 
on 1 6th July, 1955.] 

T HAVE been honoured by being asked to give the address on 
-Physics and Relativity in place of NIELS BOHR who was prevented 
from coming to Berne. 

I do not know what BOHR had in mind when he chose the title. 
I cannot remember that I have ever discussed relativity with him; 
there was in fact nothing to discuss as we agreed on all essential 
points. The title Physics and Relativity may be interpreted in 
different ways: it may mean either a review of the empirical facts 
on which relativity was built, or it may mean a survey of the 
consequences of relativity for the whole of physics. Now such a 
survey was just the purpose of this conference, and it would be 
presumptuous and quite beyond my power to summarize all the 
reports and investigations. I propose instead to give you an impres- 
sion of the situation of physics 50 years ago when EINSTEIN'S first 
papers appeared, to analyse the contents of these papers in com- 
parison with the work of his predecessors and to describe the impact 
of them on the world of physics. For most of you this is history. 
Relativity was an established theory when you began to study. 
There are very few left who like me can remember those distant 
days. For my contemporaries EINSTEIN'S theory was new and 
revolutionary, an effort was needed to assimilate it. Not everybody 
was able or willing to do so. Thus the period after EINSTEIN'S 
discovery was full of controversy, sometimes of bitter strife. I 
shall try to revive these exciting days when the foundation of 
modern physics was laid, by telling the story as it appeared to me. 

When I began to study in the year 1901 MAXWELL'S theory was 
accepted everywhere but not taught everywhere. A lecture by 
CLEMENS SCHAEFER which I attended at Breslau University was 
the first of its kind there and appeared to us to be very difficult. 
When I came to Gottingen in 1904 I attended a lecture on optics 
by WOLDEMAR VOIGT, which was based on MAXWELL'S theory; 
but that was a new venture, the transition from the elastic ether 
theory was only a few years old. The main representative of the 
modern spirit in theoretical physics at Gottingen was at that time 
MAX ABRAHAM, whose well-known book, then called Abraham- 
Foppl, now Abraham-Becker ', was our main source of information. 

189 



1 90 PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 

All this is to indicate the scientific atmosphere in which we grew up. 
NEWTON'S mechanics still dominated the field completely, in spite 
of the revolutionary discoveries made during the preceding decade. 
X-rays, radio-activity, the electron, the radiation formula and the 
quantum of energy, etc. The student was still taught and I 
think not only in Germany, but everywhere that the aim of 
physics was to reduce all phenomena to the motion of particles 
according to NEWTON'S laws, and to doubt these laws was heresy 
never attempted. 

My first encounter with the difficulties of this orthodox creed 
happened in 1905, the year which we celebrate to-day, in a seminar 
on the theory of electrons, held not by a physicist but by a mathe- 
matician, HERMANN MINKOWSKI. My memory of these long bygone 
days is of course blurred, but I am sure that in this seminar we 
discussed what was known at this period about the electrodynamics 
and optics of moving systems. We studied papers by HERTZ, 
FITZGERALD, LARMOR, LORENTZ, POINCARE, and others but also 
got an inkling of MINKOWSKI'S own ideas which were published only 
two years later. 

I have now to say some words about the work of these predecessors 
of EINSTEIN, mainly of LORENTZ and POINCARE. But I confess that 
I have not read again all their innumerable papers and books. 
When I retired from my chair at Edinburgh I settled at a quiet 
place where no scientific library is available, and I got rid of most 
of my own books. Therefore I rely a good deal on my own memory, 
assisted by a few books which I shall quote. 

H. A. LORENTZ' important papers of 1892 and 1895 on the electro- 
dynamics of moving bodies contain much of the formalism of 
relativity. However, his fundamental assumptions were quite un- 
relativistic. He assumed an ether absolutely at rest, a kind of 
materialization of NEWTON'S absolute space, and he also took 
NEWTON'S absolute time for granted. When he discovered that his 
field equations for empty space were invariant for certain linear 
transformations, by which the co-ordinates x, j>, z and the time t 
were simultaneously transformed into new parameters #', j/, z', t', 
he called them *local co-ordinates' and c local time'. These trans- 
formations, for which POINCAR later introduced the term Lorentz 
transformations, were in fact older; already in 1887 W. VOIGT 
had observed that the wave equation of the elastic theory of light 
was invariant with respect to this type of transformations. LORENTZ 
has further shown that if the interaction of matter and light was 
regarded to be due to electrons imbedded in the substance all 
observations concerning effects of the first order in ft = v/c 



PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY igi 

(v = velocity of matter, c velocity of light) could be explained, 
in particular the fact that no first order effect of the movement of 
matter could be discovered by an observer taking part in the 
motion. But there were some very accurate experiments such as 
that performed by MICHELSON first in 1881 in Potsdam, and repeated 
with higher accuracy in America in 1887 by MICHELSON and 
MORLEY, which showed that no effect of the earth motion could be 
found even to the second order in /?. To explain this FITZGERALD 
invented in 1892 the contraction hypothesis, which was at once 
taken up by LORENTZ and included in his system. Thus LORENTZ 
obtained a set of field equations for moving bodies which was in 
agreement with all known observations; it was relativistic invariant 
for processes in empty space, and approximately invariant (up to 
terms of ist order in /?) for material bodies. Still LORENTZ stuck 
to his aether at rest and the traditional absolute time. I shall return 
to this point presently. When HENRI POINCAR took up this 
investigation, he went a step further. In regard to his work I refer 
to the excellent book by Sir EDMUND WHITTAKER, A History of the 
Theories of Aether and Electricity, which was already in use as a guide 
in my student times. It has now been completely re-written. 
The second volume of the new edition deals with 'The Modern 
Theories, 1900-1926'; there you can find quotations from POIN- 
CARi's papers, some of which I have looked up in the original. 
They show that as early as 1899 he regarded it as very probable 
that absolute motion is indetectable in principle and that no 
aether exists. He formulated the same ideas in a more precise form, 
though without any mathematics, in a lecture given in 1904 to a 
Congress of Arts and Science at St. Louis, U.S.A., and he predicted 
the rise of a new mechanics which will be characterized above all 
by the rule, that no velocity can exceed the velocity of light. 

WHITTAKER was so impressed by these statements that he gave 
to the relevant chapter in his book the title 'The Relativity Theory 
of Poincare and Lorentz 3 . EINSTEIN'S contributions appear there as 
being of minor importance. 

I have tried to form an opinion about this question from my own 
recollections and with the help of a few publications available to me. 

In the happy years before the first World War the Academy of 
Gottingen had a considerable fund, called the Wolfskehl-Stiftung 
(W.-Foundation) which was given originally with the direction to 
award a prize of 100,000 Marks for the proof of FERMAT'S cele- 
brated 'Great Theorem'. Hundreds of letters, or even just post- 
cards, arrived every year claiming to contain the solution, and 
the mathematicians were kept busy to discover the error. The 



iga PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 

futility of this process became so annoying that it was decided to 
use the money for other more useful purposes, namely to invite 
distinguished scholars to lecture on current scientific problems. 
One of these series of lectures was given by HENRI POINCAR&, 
April 22nd-28th 1909, and has been published as a book by 
Teubner in 1910. I have attended these PoiNCAR^-Festspiele 
(P.-Festival), as we called it, and now refreshed my memory by 
looking through the book. The first five lectures dealt with purely 
mathematical problems; the sixth lecture had the title e La 
mecanique nouvelle'. It is a popular account of the theory of 
relativity without any formulae and with very few quotations. 
EINSTEIN and MINKOWSKI are not mentioned at all, only MICHELSON, 
ABRAHAM and LORENTZ. But the reasoning used by POINCAR! 
was just that, which EINSTEIN introduced in his first paper of 
1905, of which I shall speak presently. Does this mean that POIN- 
CAR& knew all this before EINSTEIN? It is possible, but the strange 
thing is that this Lecture definitely gives you the impression that 
he is recording LORENTZ' work. 

On the other hand LORENTZ himself has never claimed to be the 
author of the principle of relativity. The year after POINCAR'S 
visit to Gottingen we had the LoRENTZ-Festspiele. I, at the time a 
young Privatdocent, was appointed temporary assistant to the 
distinguished guest and charged with taking notes of the lectures 
and preparing them for publication. Thus I was privileged with 
having daily discussions with LORENTZ. The lectures have appeared 
in Physikalische %eitschrift (vol. 11, 1910, p. 1234). The second 
lecture begins with the words: 'Das EiNSTEiNsche Relativitats- 
prinzip hier in Gottingen zu besprechen, wo MINKOWSKI gewirkt 
hat, erscheint mir eine besonders willkommene Aufgabe 3 . 'To 
discuss EINSTEIN'S Principle of Relativity here in Gottingen where 
MINKOWSKI has taught seems to me a particularly welcome task. 6 
This suffices to show that LORENTZ himself regarded EINSTEIN as 
the discoverer of the principle of relativity. On the same page and 
also in the following sections are other remarks which reveal 
LORENTZ' reluctance to abandon the ideas of absolute space and 
time. When I visited LORENTZ a few years before his death, his 
scepticism had not changed. 

I have told you all these details because they illuminate the 
scientific scene of 50 years ago, not because I think that the question 
of priority is of great importance. 

May I now return to my own struggle with the relativity problem. 
After having graduated Dr.phil. in Gottingen I went in 1907 to 
Cambridge to learn something about the electron at the source. 



PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 1 93 

J. J. THOMSON'S lectures were very stimulating indeed; he showed 
brilliant experiments. But LARMOR'S theoretical course did not 
help me very much; I found it very hard to understand his Irish 
dialect, and what I understood seemed to me not on the level of 
MINKOWSKI'S ideas. I then returned to my home city Breslau, 
and there at last I heard the name of EINSTEIN and read his papers. 
I was working at that time on a relativistic problem, which was an 
offspring of MINKOWSKI'S seminar, and talked about it to my friends. 
One of them, STANISLAUS LORIA, a young Pole, directed my attention 
to EINSTEIN'S articles, and thus I read them. Although I was quite 
familiar with the relativistic idea and the Lorentz transformations, 
EINSTEIN'S reasoning was a revelation to me. 

Many of you may have looked up his paper 'Zur Elektrodynamik 
bewegter Korper' in Annalen der Physik (4), vol. 17, p. 811, 1905, 
and you will have noticed some peculiarities. The striking point is 
that it contains not a single reference to previous literature. It 
gives you the impression of quite a new venture. But that is, of 
course, as I have tried to explain, not true. We have EINSTEIN'S 
own testimony. Dr. CARL SEELIG, who has published a most 
charming book on Einstein und die Schweiz asked EINSTEIN which 
scientific literature had contributed most to his ideas on relativity 
during his period in Bern, and received an answer on February igth 
of this year which he published in the Technische Rundschau (N. 20, 
47. Jahrgang, Bern 6. Mai 1955); EINSTEIN wrote: 

'Es ist zweifellos, daB die spezielle Relativitatstheorie, wenn wir ihre 
Entwicklung riickschauend betrachten, im Jahre 1905 reif zur 
Entdeckung war. LORENTZ hatte schon erkannt, daB fur die Analyse 
der MAXWELLSchen Gleichungen die spater nach ihm benannte 
Transformation wesentlich sei, und POINCARE hat diese Erkenntnis 
noch vertieft. Was mich betrifft, so kannte ich nur LORENTZ 
bedeutendes Werk von 1895 "La theorie electromagnetique de 
MAXWELL" und "Versuch einer Theorie der elektrischen und optischen 
Erscheinungenin bewegten Korpern" aber nicht LORENTZ*, spatere 
Arbeiten, und auch nicht die daran anschlieBende Untersuchung 
von POINGARE. In diesem Sinne war meine Arbeit von 1905 selb- 
standig. 

'Was dabei neu war, war die Erkenntnis, daB die Bedeutung der 
Lorentztransformation iiber den Zusammenhang mit den MAXWELL- 
schen Gleichungen hinausging und das Wesen von Raum und Zeit 
im allgemeinen betraf. Auch war die Einsicht neu, daB die "Lorentz- 
Invarianz" eine allgemeine Bedingung sei fur jede physikalische 
Theorie. Das war fiir mich von besonderer Wichtigkeit, weil ich 
schon fruher erkannt hatte, daB die MAXWELLsche Theorie die Mikro- 
struktur der Strahlung nicht darstelle und deshalb nicht allgemein 
haltbar sei .' 



194 PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 

Translated: 

'There is no doubt, that the special theory of relativity, if we regard its 
development in retrospect, was ripe for discovery in 1905. LORENTZ 
had already observed that for the analysis of MAXWELL'S equations 
the transformations which later were known by his name are essential, 
and POINCARE had even penetrated deeper into these connections. 
Concerning myself, I knew only LORENTZ' important work of 1895 
(the two papers quoted above in the German text) but not LORENTZ' 
later work, nor the consecutive investigations by POINCAR. In this 
sense my work of 1905 was independent. The new feature of it was 
the realization of the fact that the bearing of the LORENTZ transforma- 
tion transcended its connection with MAXWELL'S equations and 
was concerned with the nature of space and time in general. A further 
new result was that the "Lorentz invariance" is a general condition 
for any physical theory. This was for me of particular importance 
because I had already previously found that MAXWELL'S theory did 
not account for the micro-structure of radiation and could therefore 
have no general validity .' 

This, I think, makes the situation perfectly clear. The last 
sentence of this letter is of particular importance. For it shows 
that EINSTEIN'S papers of 1905 on relativity and on the light quantum 
were not disconnected. He believed already then that MAXWELL'S 
equations were only approximately true, that the actual behaviour 
of light was more complicated and ought to be described in terms 
of light quanta (or photons, as we say to-day), but that the principle 
of relativity was more general and should be founded on con- 
siderations which would be still valid when MAXWELL'S equations 
had to be discarded and replaced by a new theory of the fine 
structure of light (our present quantum electrodynamics). 

The second peculiar feature of this first relativity paper by 
EINSTEIN is his point of departure, the empirical facts on which 
he built his theory. It is of surprising simplicity. He says that the 
usual formulation of the law of induction contains an asymmetry 
which is artificial, and does not correspond to facts. According 
to observation, the current induced depends only on the relative 
motion of the conducting wire and the magnet, while the usual 
theory explains the effect in quite different terms according to 
whether the wire is at rest and the magnet moving or vice versa. 
Then there follows a short sentence referring to the fact that all 
attempts to discover experimentally the movement of the earth 
through the aether have failed. It gives you the impression that 
MICHELSON'S experiment was not so important after all, and 
that EINSTEIN would have arrived at his relativity principle in any 
case. 



PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 195 

This principle together with the postulate that the velocity of 
light is constant, independent of the system of reference, are the 
only assumptions from which the whole theory is derived on a few 
pages. The first step is the demonstration that absolute simultaneity 
of two events at different places has no physical meaning. Then 
relative simultaneity is defined by setting the clocks at different 
places in a system of reference in such a way that a light signal 
needs the same time either way between two of them. This definition 
leads directly to the Lorentz transformations and all their conse- 
quences: the Lorentz-Fitzgerald contraction, the time dilation, 
the addition theorem of velocities, the transformation law for the 
electromagnetic field components in vacuum, the Doppler principle, 
the aberration effect, the transformation law for energy, the equa- 
tions of motion for an electron and the formulae for the longitudinal 
and transversal mass as functions of the velocity. 

But for me and many others the exciting feature of this 
paper was not so much its simplicity and completeness, but the 
audacity of challenging ISAAC NEWTON'S established philosophy, the 
traditional concepts of space and time. That distinguishes EINSTEIN'S 
work from his predecessors and gives us the right to speak of EINSTEIN'S 
theory of relativity, in spite of WHITTAKER'S different opinion. 

EINSTEIN'S second paper on relativity '1st die Tragheit eines 
Korpers von seinem Energieinhalt abhangig?' (Ann. d. Phys. (4), 
vol. 1 8, 1905, p. 639) contains on three pages a proof of the cele- 
brated formula E = me 2 expressing the equivalence of mass and 
energy, which has turned out to be of fundamental importance in 
nuclear physics, for the understanding of the structure of matter 
and of the source of stellar energy as well, and for the technical 
exploitation of nuclear energy, for bad or good. This paper also 
has become the object of priority disputes. In fact, the formula 
had been known for special cases; for instance the Austrian physicist 
F. HASENOHRL had shown already in 1904 that electromagnetic 
radiation enclosed in a vessel produced an increase of its resistance 
to acceleration, i.e. its mass, proportional to the radiation energy. 
HASENOHRL was killed in the first world war and could not object 
when his name was later misused to discredit EINSTEIN'S discovery. 
However, I shall not enter into an account of this sordid story. 
I have mentioned these matters only to make it clear that special 
relativity was, after all, not a one-man discovery. EINSTEIN'S work 
was the keystone to an arch which LORENTZ, POINCARE and others 
had built and which was to carry the structure erected by 
MINKOWSKI. I think it wrong to forget these other men, as it can 
be found in many books. Even PHILIPP FRANK'S excellent biography 



ig6 PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 

Einstein, Sein Leben und seine %eit, cannot be acquitted of this reproach, 
e.g. when he says (in Chap. 3, No. 6 of the German edition) that 
nobody before EINSTEIN had ever considered a new type of mech- 
anical law in which the velocity of light plays a prominent part. 
Both POINCARE and LORENTZ have been aware of this, and the 
relativistic expression for the mass (which contains c) has rightly 
been called LORENTZ' formula. 

To-day this formula is taken so much for granted that you can 
hardly imagine the acerbity of the controversies which raged around 
it. In 1901 W. KAUFMANN in Gottingen had by an investigation of 
the electromagnetic deflection of fast cathode rays first established 
the fact that the mass of the electron depends on its velocity. 
MAX ABRAHAM, whom I have mentioned already, took up this 
challenge and showed that the electromagnetic mass, as introduced 
by J- J- THOMSON, i.e. the self-energy of the electron's own field, 
properly developed for high velocities did indeed depend on velocity. 
He assumed the electron to be a rigid sphere; but later he also 
modified his theory by taking account of the Lorentz-Fitzgerald 
contraction, and obtained exactly the formula which Lorentz had 
already found by a simpler reasoning. As a matter of fact, the 
velocity dependence of energy and of mass has nothing at all 
to do with the structure of the body considered, but is a general 
relativistic effect. Before this became clear, many theoreticians 
wrote voluminous, not to say monstrous, papers on the electro- 
magnetic self-energy of the rigid electron G. HERGLOTZ, P. 
HERTZ, A. SOMMERFELD, and others. My first scientific attempt was 
also in this direction; however, I did not assume the electron to be 
rigid in the classical sense, but tried to define relativistic rigidity 
by generalizing the Lorentz electron for accelerated motion, with 
the help of the methods I had learned from MINKOWSKI. 

To-day all these efforts appear rather wasted; quantum theory 
has shifted the point of view, and at present the tendency is to cir- 
cumvent the problem of self-energy rather than to solve it. But 
one day it will return to the centre of the scene. 

MINKOWSKI published his paper 'Die Grundlagen fur die elektro- 
magnetischen Vorgange in bewegten Korpern' in 1 907. It contained 
the systematic presentation of his formal unification of space and 
time into a four-dimensional 'world' with a pseudo-euclidean geo- 
metry, for which a vector- and tensor calculus is developed. This 
calculus, with some modifications, soon became the standard method 
of all relativistic investigations. Moreover, MINKOWSKI'S paper 
contained important new results : a set of equations for the electro- 
magnetic field in moving material bodies which is exactly invariant 



PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY ig7 

with respect to LORENTZ transformation, not only a first approxi- 
mation as LORENTZ' slightly different equations; further a new 
approach to the mechanical equations of motion. 

In the beginning of 1908 I had the audacity to send my manu- 
script on the electron to MINKOWSKI, and he was kind enough to 
answer. On September sist of the same year I listened at Cologne 
to his famous lecture 'Raum und Zeit', in which he explained his 
ideas in popular form to the members of the Naturforscher-Ver- 
sammlung. He invited me to come to Gottingen and to join him 
in further work. So I did; but alas, after a few weeks our colla- 
boration ended through MINKOWSKI'S sudden death. It fell to me 
to sift his unpublished papers, one of which I succeeded to recon- 
struct and to publish. 

My first meeting with EINSTEIN happened in the following year, 
1909, at the Naturforscher-Versammlung in Salzburg. There 
EINSTEIN gave a lecture with the title 'Dber die neueren Umwand- 
lungen, welche unsere Anschauungen iiber die Natur des Lichtes 
erfahren haben', which means obviously the introduction of the 
light quantum. I also gave a talk 'Die Dynamik des Elektrons im 
System des Relativitatsprinzips 5 , This seems to me rather amusing: 
EINSTEIN had already proceeded beyond special relativity which 
he left to minor prophets., while he himself pondered about the 
new riddles arising from the quantum structure of light, and of 
course about gravitation and general relativity which at that time 
was not ripe for general discussion. 

From this time on I saw EINSTEIN occasionally at conferences 
and exchanged a few letters with him. He became professor at the 
University of Zurich in 1909, then at Prague in 1910 and returned 
to Zurich, as professor at the Polytechnicum in 1912. Already in 
the following year he went to Berlin, where the Prussian Academy 
had offered him a special chair, vacated by the death of VAN't 
HOFF, with no teaching obligations, and with other privileges. This 
invitation was mainly due to the efforts of MAX PLANCK who was 
deeply interested in relativity and had contributed important papers 
on relativistic mechanics and thermodynamics. Two years later, 
in spring 1915, I was also called to Berlin by PLANCK, to assist him 
in his teaching. The following four years have been amongst the 
most memorable of my life, not because the first World War was 
raging with all its sorrows, excitements, privations and indignities, 
but because I was near to PLANCK and EINSTEIN. 

It was the only period when I saw EINSTEIN very frequently, at 
times almost daily, and when I could watch the working of his 
mind and learn his ideas on physics and on many other subjects. 



198 PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 

It was the time when general relativity was finally formulated. 
Now this was, in contrast to the special theory, a real one-man 
work. It began with a paper published as early as December, 
1907, which contains the principle of equivalence, the only empirical 
pillar on which the whole imposing structure of general relativity 
was built. 

When speaking of the physical facts which EINSTEIN used in 1905 
for his special relativity I said that it was the law of electromagnetic 
induction which seemed to have guided EINSTEIN more than even 
MICHELSON'S experiment. Now the induction law was at that time 
about 70 years old (FARADAY discovered it in 1834), everybody had 
known all along that the effect depended only on relative motion, 
but nobody had taken offence at the theory not accounting for this 
circumstance. 

Now the case of the equivalence principle is very similar, only 
that the critical empirical fact has been known by everybody far 
longer, namely about 250 years. GALILEO had found that all 
bodies move with the same acceleration under terrestrial gravity, 
and NEWTON generalized this for the mutual gravitational attraction 
of celestial bodies. This fact, namely, that the inertial and the 
gravitational mass are equal, was taken as a peculiar property of 
NEWTON'S force, and nobody seems to have pondered about it. 

Special relativity had restored the special r61e and the equivalence 
of the inertial systems of Newtonian mechanics for the whole of 
physics; absolute motion was indetectable as long as no accelera- 
tions occurred. But the inertia effects, the centrifugal forces and 
corresponding electromagnetic phenomena, which appear in accel- 
erated, for instance rotating, systems could be described only in 
terms of absolute space. This seemed to be intolerable to EINSTEIN. 
Brooding over it, he noticed that the equality of inertial and gravi- 
tational mass implied that an observer in a closed box could not 
decide whether a non-uniformity of the motion of a body in the box 
was due to an acceleration of the whole box or to an external gravi- 
tational field. This gave him the clue for general relativity. 
EINSTEIN postulated that this equivalence should hold as a general 
principle for all natural phenomena, not only mechanical motion. 
Thus he arrived in 1911 at the conclusion that a beam of light 
must be bent in a gravitational field and suggested at once that his 
simple formula of deflexion could be experimentally checked by 
observing the position of fixed stars near the sun during a total 
eclipse. 

The actual development of the theory was a tremendous task, 
for a new branch of mathematics, quite unfamiliar to physicists, 



PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY igg 

had to be used. Some more conservative physicists, ABRAHAM, 
MIE, NORDSTROM and others tried to develop from EINSTEIN'S 
equivalence principle a coherent scalar theory of the gravitational 
field, with little success. EINSTEIN himself was the only one who 
discovered the right mathematical tool in RIEMANN'S geometry, as 
extended by RICCI and LEVi-CrvrrA, and he found in his old friend 
MARCEL GROSSMANN a skilful collaborator. But it took several years, 
until 1915, to finish this work. 

I remember that on my honeymoon in 1913 I had in my luggage 
some reprints of EINSTEIN'S papers which absorbed my attention 
for hours, much to the annoyance of my bride. These papers seemed 
to me fascinating, but difficult and almost frightening. When I 
met EINSTEIN in Berlin in 1915 the theory was much improved and 
crowned by the explanation of the anomaly of the perihelion of 
Mercury, discovered by LEVERRIER. I learned it not only from the 
publications but from numerous discussions with EINSTEIN which 
had the effect that I decided never to attempt any work in this 
field. The foundation of general relativity appeared to me then, 
and it still does, the greatest feat of human thinking about Nature, 
the most amazing combination of philosophical penetration, physical 
intuition and mathematical skill. But its connections with experience 
were slender. It appealed to me like a great work of art, to be 
enjoyed and admired from a distance. 

According to my interpretation of the title of this lecture I shall 
not enter into a discussion of the empirical confirmation of the 
special and the general theory of relativity, as I am no expert, and 
as others have spoken of it already I shall only just mention the 
most striking events. 

In 1915 SOMMERFELD'S relativistic theory of the fine structure of 
the hydrogen lines was published. It is based on the mathematical 
result, that the dependence of mass on velocity produces a pre- 
cession of the perihelion of the elliptic orbit. It is quite interesting 
that POINCARE had already considered this effect to explain 
LEVERRJER'S anomaly in the motion of the planet Mercury; a 
remark about this is contained in POINGARE'S lecture in Gottingen 
quoted before. The result was of course negative, as the velocity of 
Mercury is much too small compared with that of light. It is 
different with the electron moving around a nucleus and, in com- 
bination with the quantization laws of BOHR and SOMMERFELD, 
this led to the explanation of the splitting of the hydrogen lines. 

The modern version of the theory of the hydrogen spectrum is 
based on DIRAC'S relativistic wave equation and has recently been 
much refined with the help of quantum electrodynamics. 



20O PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 

Another striking result of relativity combined with EINSTEIN'S 
idea of light quanta is the theory of the Compton effect. 

The time dilation effect was directly confirmed as the transversal 
DOPPLER effect on hydrogen canal rays in 1938 by IVES and 
STTEVELL, and with higher accuracy in 1939 by RUCHARDT and 
OTTING. It plays an important part in the modern research on 
mesons in cosmic rays where the observed lifetime of a meson may 
be a hundred times as large as the intrinsic one in consequence of 
the large velocities. 

At present special relativity is taken for granted, the whole 
of atomic physics is so merged with it, so soaked in it, that it would 
be quite meaningless to pick out particular effects as confirmations 
of EINSTEIN'S theory. The situation in general relativity is different; 
all the three effects predicted by EINSTEIN exist, but the question of 
quantitative agreement between the theory and observation is 
still under discussion. However, the importance of general relativity 
lies in the revolution which it has produced in cosmology. It started 
in 1917 when EINSTEIN generalized his field equations by adding 
the so-called cosmological term and showed that a solution exists 
representing a closed universe. This suggestion of a finite, but 
unbounded, space is one of the very greatest ideas about the nature 
of the world which ever has been conceived. It solved the mysterious 
fact why the system of stars did not disperse and thin out, which it 
would do if space were infinite; it gave a physical meaning to 
MACK'S principle which postulated that the law of inertia should 
not be regarded as a property of empty space but as an effect of 
the total system of stars, and it opened the way to the modern con- 
cept of the expanding universe. Here general relativity found again 
contact with observation through the work of the astronomers 
SHAPLEY, HUBBLE and many others. To-day cosmology is an 
extensive science which has produced innumerable publications and 
books, of which I know little. Thus I am compelled to omit just 
that aspect of EINSTEIN'S work which may be regarded as his 
greatest achievement. 

May I, instead, tell you something about my personal relations 
with EINSTEIN in those bygone days and about the divergence of 
opinion which arose in the end between us in regard to the ultimate 
principles of physics. 

The discussions which we had in Berlin ranged far beyond rela- 
tivity, and even beyond physics at large. As the first world war 
was going on politics played of course a central part. But much 
as I would like to speak about these things I have to restrict myself 
to physics. 



PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 2OI 

EINSTEIN was at that time working with DE HAAS on experiments 
about the so-called gyromagnetic effect, which proved the existence 
of AMPERE'S molecular currents. He was also deeply interested in 
quantum theory but worried by its paradoxes. 

In 1919 I became v. LAUE'S successor at Frankfurt, and my 
companionship with EINSTEIN ceased. But we visited one another 
often and had a lively correspondence, of which I shall give you a 
few examples. It was the time when EINSTEIN suddenly became 
world famous, and his theory as well as his personality the object 
of fanatical controversy. 

Just before the war a German expedition had gone to Russia to 
investigate EINSTEIN'S prediction of the deflexion of light by the sun 
during an eclipse; they were stopped by the outbreak of hostilities, 
and became prisoners of war. Now after the war two British 
expeditions went out for the same purpose, under the direction of 
Sir ARTHUR EDDINGTON, and they were successful. It is quite 
impossible to describe the stir which this event produced in the 
whole world. EINSTEIN became at once the most famous and 
popular figure, the man who had broken through the wall of hatred 
and united the scientists to a common effort, the man who had 
replaced ISAAC NEWTON'S system of the world by another and 
better one. But at the same time an opposition, which had already 
been apparent while I was in Berlin, grew under the leadership of 
PHILIPP LENARD and JOHANNES STARK. It was springing from the 
most absurd mixture of scientific conservatism and prejudice with 
racial and political emotions, due to EINSTEIN'S Jewish descent and 
pacifistic, antimilitaristic convictions. Here a few samples from 
EINSTEIN'S letters; one of June 4th 1919 begins with physics: 

*. . . Die Quantentheorie lost bei rnir ganz ahnliche Empfindungen 
axis wie bei Ihnen. Man miiBte sich eigentlich der Erfolge schamen, 
weil sie nach dem jesuitischen Grundsatze gewonnen sind: "Die 
eine Hand darf nicht wissen, was die andre tut . . .".' 

'. . , The quantum theory provokes in me quite similar sensations as 
in you. One ought really to be ashamed of the successes, as they are 
obtained with the help of the Jesuitic rule: "One hand must not 
know what the other does".' 

and then, a few lines below, he continues about politics: 

'. . . Darf ein hartgesottener -X"-Bruder und Determinist mit thranen- 
feuchten Augen sagen, daB er den Glauben an die Menschen verloren 
hat? Gerade das triebhafte Verhalten der Menschen von heute in 
politischen Dingen ist geeignet, den Glauben an den Determinismus 
recht lebendig zu machen . . .' 



2O2 PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 

*. . . Can a hardboiled -ST-brother (= mathematician; we used the 
expression "ixen", "to AT", for "calculating") say with tears in his 
eyes that he has lost his faith in the human race? Just the instinctive 
behaviour of contemporary people in political affairs is apt to revive 
the belief in determinism . . .' 

You see that his deterministic philosophy which later created a 
gulf between him and the majority of physicists was not restricted 
to science but extended to human affairs as well. 

At this time the inflation in Germany began to become serious. 
In my department STERN and GERLAGH were preparing their well- 
known experiments, but hampered by the lack of funds. I decided 
to give a series of popular lectures on relativity with an entrance 
fee, using the general craze for information about this subject to 
raise funds for our researches. The plan was successful, the lectures 
were crowded, and when they appeared as a book three editions 
were quickly sold. EINSTEIN acknowledged my efforts by offering 
me the friendly 'Du J instead of the formal e Sie* in a letter of Novem- 
ber gth 1919, which also contains some suggestion how the Jews 
should react to the antisemitic drive going on: 

'Also von jetzt ab soil Du gesagt werden unter uns, wenn Du es 
erlaubst . . . Ich wiirde es fiir vernunftig halten, wenn die Juden 
selbst Geld sammelten, um jiidischen Forschern auBerhalb der Univer- 
sitaten Unterstiitzung und Lehrgelegenheit zu bieten . . .' 

'Well, from now on the "Thou" shall be used between us, if thou 
agreest ... I should think it reasonable if the Jews themselves would 
collect money in order to give Jewish scholars financial support and 
teaching facility outside the universities . . .' 

There appeared attacks against EINSTEIN by well known scientists 
and philosophers in the Frankfurter ^eitung which aroused my 
pugnacity. I answered in a rather sharp article. EINSTEIN seems 
to have been pleased with it for he wrote on December 9th 1919: 

'Dein ausgezeichneter Artikel in der Frankfurter Zeitwg hat mich sehr 
gefreut. Nun aber wirst Du, gerade wie ich, wenn auch in schwa- 
cherem Masstab, von Presse- und sonstigem Gelichter verfolgt Bei 
mir ist es so arg, dafi ich kaum mehr schnaufen, geschweige zu 
vernunftiger Arbeit kommen kann . . .' 

'Your excellent article in the Frankfurter %eitung has given me great 
pleasure. Now you as well as I will be persecuted by gangs of pressmen 
and others though to a smaller degree. With me it is so bad that I 
can hardly breathe any more, to say nothing of doing reasonable 
work . . .' 



PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 2O3 

And about a year later (September gth 1920) : 

'. . . Wie bei dem Mann im Marchen alles zu Gold wurde, was er 
beriihrte, so wird bei mir alles zum Zeitungsgeschrei: Suum 
cuique . . .* 

e . . . Just as with the man in the fairy tale everything he touched was 
transformed into gold, with me everything becomes newspaper noise. 
Suum cuique . . .' 

If you are interested in that curious period when a whole world 
was excited about a physical theory which nobody understood, 
and when everywhere people were split into pro- and contra-EiN- 
STEIN factions you can find an excellent account in the biography 
by PHILIPP FRANK quoted before. 

However, scientific problems regained their proper place in our 
correspondence. In the same year (March 3rd 1920) EINSTEIN 
wrote: 

*Ich brute in meiner freien Zeit immer iiber dem Quantenproblem 
vom Standpunkte der Relativitat. Ich glaube nicht, dafi die Theorie 
das Kontinuum wird entbehren konnen. Es will mir aber nicht 
gelingen, meiner Lieblingsidee, die Quantentheorie aus einer Uber- 
bestimmung durch Differentialgleichungen zu verstehen, greifbare 
Gestalt zu geben . . .' 

'I always brood in my free time about the quantum problem from 
the standpoint of relativity. I do not think that the theory will have to 
discard the continuum. But I was unsuccessful, so far, to give tangible 
shape to my favourite idea, to understand the quantum theory with 
the help of differential equations by using conditions of over-deter- 
mination . . .' 

Already at that time we discussed whether quantum theory could 
be reconciled with causality. Here a sentence from EINSTEIN'S 
letter of January syth 1920: 

*. . . Das mit der Kausalitat plagt mich auch viel. 1st die quanten- 
hafte Licht- Absorption und -Emission wohl jemals im Sinne der 
vollstandigen Kausalitatsforderung erfassbar oder bleibt ein statistischer 
Rest? Ich muss gestehen, dass mir da der Mut einer "Oberzeugung 
fehlt. Ich verzichte aber sehr, sehr tmgern auf volktandige Kausal- 
itat . . .' 

'That question of causality worries me also a lot. Will the quantum 
absorption and emission of light ever be grasped in the sense of complete 
causality, or will there remain a statistical residue? I have to confess, 
that I lack the courage of a conviction. However I should be very, 
very loath to abandon complete causality . . ." 



204 PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 

From that time on our scientific ways parted more and more. I 
went to Gottingen and came in contact with NIELS BOHR, PAULI 
and HEISENBERG. When in 1927 quantum mechanics was deve- 
loped, I hoped of course that EINSTEIN would agree, but was 
disappointed. Here a quotation from one of his letters (December 
1 2th 1926): 

*. . . Die Quantenmechanik ist sehr achtunggebietend. Aber 
eine innere Stimme sagt mir, dass das doch nicht der wahre Jakob 
ist. Die Theorie liefert viel, aber dem Geheimnis des Alten bringt 
sie uns kaum naher. Jedenfalls bin ich iiberzeugt, daB der nicht 
wiirfelt . . . Ich plage mich damit herum, die Bewegungsgleichungen 
von als Singularitaten aufgefassten materiellen Punkten aus den 
DifFerentialgleichungen der allgemeinen Relativitat abzuleiten . . .* 

'The quantum mechanics is very imposing. But an inner voice tells 
me that it is still not the true Jacob [a German colloquialism.]. The 
theory yields much, but it hardly brings us nearer to the secret of the 
Old One. In any case I am convinced that he does not throw dice . . 
I am toiling at deriving the equations of motion of material particles 
regarded as singularities from the differential equations of general 
relativity . . .' 

The last sentence refers to a paper which was finished much 
later at Princeton in collaboration with BENESH HOFFMANN and 
LEOPOLD INFELD, EINSTEIN'S last great contribution to relativity. 
The assumption made in the original theory, that a free particle 
(e.g. a celestial body) moves on a geodesic turned out to be un- 
necessary, it could be derived from the field equations by a subtle 
procedure of successive approximations. These very deep and 
important investigations have been further developed by FOGK 
and INFELD. 

The first part of the letter quoted refers to EINSTEIN'S refusal to 
accept statistical laws in physics as final; he speaks of the dice- 
playing God, an expression which he has used later very often in 
discussion and letters. 

During the last period of his life in Princeton he concentrated 
all his powers and energies on developing a new foundation of physics 
in conformity with his fundamental philosophical convictions, 
namely that it must be possible to think of the external world as 
existing independently of the observing subject, and that the laws 
governing this objective world are strictly causal, in the sense of 
deterministic. This was the aim of his unified field theories, of 
which he published several versions, always hoping that the quantum 
principles would in the end turn out to be a consequence of his 
field equations. 



PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 2O5 

I cannot say much about these attempts, as right from the begin- 
ning I just did not believe in their success and therefore did not 
study his difficult papers with sufficient care. I think that quantum 
mechanics has followed up EINSTEIN'S original philosophy, which 
led him to tremendous success, more closely than he did himself 
in his later period. 

What is this lesson we learned from him? He himself has told us 
that he learned it from ERNST MACH, and therefore the positivists 
have claimed him to be one of them. I do not think this is true, 
if positivism is the doctrine that the purpose of science is the 
description of interrelation of sense impressions. EINSTEIN'S leading 
principle was simply that something of which you could think and 
form a concept, but which from its very nature could not be sub- 
mitted to an experimental test (like the simultaneity of events at 
distant places) has no physical meaning. 

The quantum effects showed that this holds for a great many 
concepts of atomic physics, but EINSTEIN refused to apply his 
criterion to these cases. Thus he rejected the current interpretation 
of quantum mechanics, though it follows his own general teaching, 
and tried quite a different way, rather remote from experience. 
He had achieved his greatest success by relying on just one empirical 
fact known to every schoolboy. Yet now he tried to do without 
any empirical facts, by pure thinking. He believed in the power 
of reason to guess the laws according to which God has built the 
world. He was not alone in this conviction. One of the principal 
exponents of it was EDDINGTON in his later papers and books. In 
1943 I published a pamphlet with the title Experiment and Theory 
in Physics (Cambridge University Press) in which I tried to analyse 
the situation and to refute EDDINGTON'S claims. I sent a copy to 
EINSTEIN and received a very interesting reply which unfortunately 
has been lost; but I remember a phrase like this : *Your thundering 
against the Hegelism is quite amusing, but I shall continue with 
my endeavours to guess God's ways.' A man of EINSTEIN'S greatness 
who has achieved so much by thinking, has the right to go to the 
limit of the a priori method. Current physics has not followed him; 
it has continued to accumulate empirical facts, and to interpret 
them in a way which EINSTEIN thoroughly disliked. For him a 
potential or a field component was a real natural object which 
changed according to definite deterministic laws. Modern physics 
operates with wave functions which, in their mathematical behavi- 
our, are very similar to classical potentials but do not represent real 
objects; they serve for determining the probability of finding real 
objects, whether these are particles or electromagnetic potentials, 



206 PHYSICS AND RELATIVITY 

or other physical quantities. EINSTEIN made many attempts to 
prove the inconsistency of this theory with the help of ingenious 
examples and models, and NIELS BOHR took infinite trouble to refute 
these attacks; he has given a charming report about his discussions 
with EINSTEIN in the book Einstein, Philosopher-Scientist (The Library 
of Living Philosophers, Vol. 7, p. 199). 

I saw EINSTEIN the last time about 1930, and although our 
correspondence continued I do not feel competent to speak about 
the last phase of EINSTEIN'S life and work. I hope that Professor 
PAULI will tell us something about it. I conclude my address by 
apologizing that it was so long. But my friendship with EINSTEIN 
was one of the greatest experiences of my life, and 'Ex abundantia 
enim cordis os loquitur', or in good Scots: 'Neirest the heart, 
neirest the mouth'. 



DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE 
OF THE ATOMIC AGE 

[Lecture given to a meeting of journalists held at the Protestant Theological 
Academy of Loccum Abbey, Niedersachsen, Germany, on- March i8th, I955> 
and repeated at several other meetings during the summer of 1955.] 

IN following the invitation to speak about the Atomic Age, 
its development and essence, I do not think that I am intended 
to enlarge upon physical discoveries and their applications to 
technological and military ends, but rather on what appears to 
me the historical roots of these discoveries and their consequences 
upon the destiny of Man. But a scientist like myself has little time 
for historical studies; I have to rely on the fact that during my 
long life of more than 70 years I have witnessed a section of modern 
history and pondered about it. Moreover, I have read or at least 
scanned a few books which may be useful for my purpose. For 
instance, I remember from my student's days SPENGLER'S Decline 
of the West (Untergang des Abendlandes) . I have also read a little 
in ARNOLD TOYNBEE'S great work, and listened to some of his 
Gifford Lectures given at Edinburgh a few years ago. I mention 
these two authors together because both share the opinion that 
there are regularities or even laws in human history which can 
be revealed by a comparative study of different groups of nations 
and civilizations. What I actually know of European history is 
essentially due to a book much used at British schools and elementary 
University courses because of its admirable style and clarity, 
H. A. L. FISHER'S A History of Europe. His standpoint can be seen 
from quoting a few lines of his Preface. 

'One intellectual excitement has, however, been denied to me. Men 
wiser and more learned than I have discerned in history a plot, a 
rhythm, a predetermined pattern. These harmonies are concealed 
from me. I can see only one emergency following upon another as 
wave follows upon wave, only one great fact with respect to which, 
since it is unique, there can be no generalizations, only one safe rule 
for the historian: that he should recognize in the development of 
human destinies the play of the contingent and the unforeseen. This 
is not a doctrine of cynicism and despair. The fact of progress is 
written plain and large on the page of history; but progress is not a 
law of nature. The ground gained by one generation may be lost by 
the next. Thoughts of men may flow into the channels which lead to 
disaster and barbarism.* 

207 



208 DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 

There are apparently two historical schools, one of which believes 
that the historical course of events obeys laws and has a meaning, 
and another which denies this. 

As a scientist I am accustomed to search for regularities and laws 
in natural phenomena. I beg your forebearance if I consider also 
the problem in hand from this standpoint, yet in quite a different 
manner from that used by the two historians mentioned. 

The dawn of a new historical age, for instance the transition 
from antiquity to the mediaeval period, is obviously not noticed by 
those who are alive at that time. Everything goes on without 
break, the life of the son is not much different from that of the 
father. The division into periods and ages is an invention of the 
historians made for the purpose of finding their way in the chaos 
of events. Even the beginning of the scientific-technological period 
in which we are living was a slow process stretching over more 
than a hundred years and hardly noticed by the people of that 
day. 

At present things appear to be different. During the time of a 
few years something new has arrived which is transforming our 
lives. This new feature includes simultaneously a horrible threat 
and a brilliant hope: the threat of self-destruction of the human 
race, the hope of earthly paradise. And this is not a revelation of 
religious prophets or of philosophical sages, but these two possi- 
bilities are presented to the human race for choosing by science, 
the most sober activity of the mind. The threat of destruction in 
particular is demonstrated by impressive examples Hiroshima 
and Nagasaki which should suffice to convince. But I wish to 
say right from the beginning that the atom bombs used there were 
children's toys compared with the thermo-nuclear weapons deve- 
loped since. I myself have not taken any part in the development 
of this chapter of science nuclear physics. But I know enough 
of it to say that it is not a question of a simple multiplication of 
destructive power, which would lead to the annihilation of a 
certain number of unfortunate people, while a much greater 
number of more fortunates would escape. It is a radical and 
sweeping change of the situation. Already to-day the stock of 
A-, H- and U-bombs in the United States and in Russia is probably 
sufficient to wipe out mutually all larger cities in both countries, 
and presumably in addition all remaining centres of civilization, 
since almost all countries are more or less attached to one of the 
giant powers. But much worse things are in preparation, perhaps 
already available for application: for instance the cobalt bomb 
which produces a radioactive dust spreading over wide areas and 



DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 2O9 

killing all living creatures therein. Particularly sinister are the 
after-effects of radioactive radiation on generations unborn; 
mutations may be induced which lead to a degeneration of the 
human race. OTTO HAHN whose discovery of the fission of uranium 
has set in motion this development without his participation and 
much against his wish recently described the true aspect of the 
situation in a radio lecture which has been published and widely 
read; I need to add nothing to it. There he has also mentioned 
the useful applications of nuclear physics, namely, the generation 
of energy, the production of isotopes as instruments in medicine 
and technology, and so on. These may indeed become a blessing 
in future days, but only if these future days exist. We are standing 
at a crossroad as the human race has never met before on her way 
through the centuries. 

This 'to be or not to be* is, however, only a symptom of a state 
of our mental development. We have to ask: What is the deeper 
cause of the dilemma in which man has been involved? 

The fundamental fact is the discovery that the matter which we 
and all things around us are made of is not solid and indestructible, 
but unstable, an explosive. We are all sitting, in the true sense of 
the word, on a powder barrel. This barrel has, it is true, rather 
strong walls, and we needed a few thousand years to drill a hole 
into it. To-day we have just got through and may at any moment 
blow ourselves sky-high with a match. 

This dangerous situation is simply a matter of fact. I shall return 
to the scientific facts later and describe them in more learned 
terms. But first I want to discuss the question: Would it not have 
been possible to let the barrel untouched and to sit peacefully 
upon it without caring about its content? Or, without the use of 
this metaphor: Could the human race not live and flourish without 
investigating into the structure of matter and thus to conjure up 
the peril of self-destruction ? 

To answer this question one needs a definite philosophical out- 
look on history. I am hardly entitled to claim any knowledge 
in this field, yet, as I proposed before, permit me to try and tackle 
it with the methods of a scientist. 

Then the situation appears like this. Man is often defined as the 
"thinking animal'. His rise depends on his ability to collect expe- 
riences and to act accordingly. Single individuals or groups of 
such lead the way, others follow and learn. This was an anonymous 
process through centuries; we know nothing of the men of early 
ages who invented the first tools and weapons, who learned cattle 
breeding and agriculture, who developed the languages and the 
art of writing. But we may be sure that there was a permanent 



21 DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 

struggle between the minority of progressively-minded people and 
the conservative crowd, as we observe it since written documents 
exist. The total number of men is large and increases with each 
improvement of the conditions of life. If the percentage of the 
gifted remains roughly constant their absolute number grows in the 
same rate as the total number of men. Simultaneously with each 
technical invention the possibility of new combinations increases. 
Hence the situation is similar to that of the calculus of compound 
interest: If the interest is added to the capital this increases, and 
with it the next instalment of interest, hence again the capital, and 
so on ad infinitum. One has what the mathematicians call an exponen- 
tial increase. 

This is, of course, only correct for the average, it is a statistical 
law. I am convinced that the laws of statistics are valid in history 
just as for the game of roulette, or in atomic physics, in stellar 
astronomy, in genetics and so on namely, in all cases where one 
has to do with large numbers. This may be taken as an interpreta- 
tion of the meaning of the sentence from FISHER'S History of Europe, 
quoted above: 'The fact of progress is written plain and large on 
the page of history'. But if he continues, but progress is not a law 
of nature' he appears to have applied an obsolete notion of the 
essence of natural laws, namely, that they are rigorously causal 
and deterministic and permit no exception. We know to-day that 
most of the laws of nature are of a statistical kind and permit 
deviations; we physicists call these 'fluctuations'. 

As this idea is not familiar to everybody allow me to illustrate 
it by a simple example. The air which we all breathe seems to be 
a thin, continuous substance of uniform density. But investigations 
with intricate instruments have shown that actually the air consists 
of innumerable molecules (mainly of two kinds, oxygen and hydro- 
gen) which fly about and collide with one another. The appearance 
of continuity is a consequence of the grossness of our senses which 
register only the average behaviour of big numbers of molecules. 
But then the question arises: why is the average distribution uniform 
in the chaotic dance of molecules? Or in other words, why is there 
the same number of molecules in two equal volumes of space? 
The answer is that there is never exactly the same number of 
molecules in equal volumes, but only approximately, and this is the 
consequence of a simple result of statistics, according to which this 
approximately uniform distribution has an overwhelming probability 
as compared with any others. But there are deviations which can 
be observed if the two volumes compared are sufficiently small. 
Particles suspended in the air, for instance pollen from plants or 



DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 211 

cigarette smoke, perform tiny irregular zig-zag motions which can 
be seen in a microscope; the explanation given by EINSTEIN of 
this effect, called Brownian movement, is simply that the number 
of air molecules hitting such a tiny, but microscopically visible, 
particle in opposite directions is not exactly equal in any short 
time interval, hence the particle is pushed about through the 
fluctuations of the average recoil. In principle there is no limit 
to the size of these fluctuations, but a statistical law makes it 
extremely improbable that very large deviations occur. Otherwise 
it might happen that the density of the air near to my mouth might 
become so small for a few minutes that I would suffocate. I am 
not afraid of this because the probability of its occurrence is 
immensely small. 

I think that uniformity in history is due to the same statistical 
law. But ordinary history deals generally with small groups and 
short times; then the statistical uniformity does not strike the eye, 
but the fluctuations which appear chaotic and senseless. I wonder 
whether TOYNBEE'S speculations may not be regarded as an attempt 
to discover regularities in the fluctuations. 

However that may be, one conclusion from this consideration 
seems to me inescapable. 

The process of gathering and applying knowledge seen as an 
endeavour of the whole human race over long periods of time must 
follow the statistical law of exponential increase and cannot be 
halted. 

On the other hand, if only a restricted space on earth and a 
restricted period are considered, say a nation or a group of peoples 
in the period of a few hundred years, nothing of that process may 
be visible, even a loss of the achievements and a retrogression. But 
then the power of the human mind will manifest itself at another 
place of the world and at another time. 

Let me illustrate this by a few historical reminiscences. The 
decisive step on the way to atomic physics was made about 2,500 
years ago; I mean the speculations of the Greek school of natural 
philosophy, THALES, ANAXIMANDER, ANAXIMENES, especially the 
atomists LEUKIPPOS and DEMOGRITOS. They were the first who 
thought about Nature without expecting an immediate material 
advantage, driven by a pure desire of knowledge. They postulated 
the existence of natural laws and tried to reduce the variety of 
matter to the play of configuration and motion of invisible, un- 
changeable, equal particles. It is not easy to apprehend the immense 
superiority of this idea over all conceptions current at that time in 
the rest of the world. Together with the grand mathematics of the 



212 DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 

Greeks this idea might have led already at that early period to a 
decisive scientific- technological advance had not the social condi- 
tions been unfavourable. These Greek gentlemen lived in a world 
which venerated the harmony and beauty of body and mind. They 
despised manual work which was the task of slaves, and thus they 
neglected experiment which cannot be done without soiling one's 
hands. Thus no empirical foundation of the ideas was attempted, 
nor their technical application, which might have saved the antique 
world from the assault of the barbarians. 

After the great migration of people the Christian Church erected 
a totalitarian system ill-disposed to all innovations. Yet the fire 
kindled by the Greeks smouldered under the ashes. It lay hidden 
in the books which were kept and copied in many monasteries and 
stored in the libraries of Byzantium, and it flared up to a bright 
flame through the Arabian scholars who even created essentially 
new things in mathematics and astronomy and who guarded the 
Greek tradition until the time was ripe. The Byzantians who fled 
before the Turks to Italy did bring with their books not only the 
knowledge of classical antiquity but also the idea of research. Thus 
came the time of discoveries and inventions which secured Europe's 
preponderance for a few centuries. A parallel development, per- 
haps of even older origin, took place in China. I know little about 
it, but there is a new comprehensive book by J. NEEDHAM, well 
known biologist at Cambridge, England, which gives a detailed 
account of it. During and after the European Renaissance, China 
was just in a state of rest or stagnation, and thus it came about that 
Europe was ahead for a few centuries. I had enough Chinese, also 
Japanese and Indian, students to be convinced that these nations 
are in no way inferior to us in scientific talent. 

There are two conclusions to be drawn from these considerations. 
Firstly, it is quite absurd to believe the crisis in the existence of the 
human race, the dawn of the atomic age, might have been avoided, 
or the further development of dangerous knowledge might be 
inhibited. HITLER has tried to choke what he called 'Jewish 
Physics', the Soviets tried the same with Mendelian genetics, both 
without any success, to their own detriment. 

Secondly, the suddenness of the appearance of the critical situa- 
tion is partly an historical accident, but mainly a deception of 
perspective distortion. The knowledge of Nature and the power 
springing from it are steadily growing, though with fluctuations 
and retrogressions, but in the average with the continuously in- 
creasing acceleration characteristic for a self-supporting (exponen- 
tial) process. Thus the day had necessarily to come when the 



DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 213 

change of the conditions of life produced by this process would be 
considerable during one single generation and therefore would 
appear as a catastrophe. This impression of a catastrophe is in- 
creased by the complications due to the fact that there are peoples 
which have not taken part in the technical development and have 
to adapt themselves to it without proper preparation. 

It is our generation which gathers the harvest sown by the Greek 
atomists. The final result of physical research is a confirmation of 
their fundamental idea that the material world is essentially com- 
posed of equal elementary particles whose configuration and inter- 
action produces the variety of phenomena. But this simple des- 
cription is, of course, only a crude condensation of an abundance 
of experimental results, and becomes, by supplementary features, 
in the end very complicated. 

Those elementary particles are called nucleons, because by 
clotting together they form the atomic nucleus. The chemical 
atoms are neither invisible (as the name indicates), nor all identical 
for a definite chemical element, as believed during the last century. 
This is a consequence of the fact that a nucleon may be either 
electrically neutral then it is called neutron or may carry a 
positive elementary charge then it is called proton. The chemical 
atoms consist of a nucleus which is an extremely dense agglomera- 
tion of neutrons and protons (hence it is positively charged), and 
an extended cloud of negative electric particles, called electrons, 
surrounding the nucleus. The electron has a very small mass 
compared with the nucleon, but the same charge as the proton, 
with the opposite sign. The number of electrons in the cloud is 
equal to that of the protons in the nucleus so that the whole atom 
is electrically neutral. The electronic cloud determines the chemical 
and most of the physical properties of the atom. Atoms which 
have the same number of protons and therefore the same number of 
electrons in the cloud are chemically, and in most respects also 
physically, indistinguishable, even if the number of neutrons in the 
nucleus may differ. Such almost identical atoms, which differ only 
by the number of neutrons, i.e. by their mass (weight) are called 
isotopes. 

The elements of ordinary chemistry and physics are mixtures of 
isotopes. The laws which govern the structure of the electronic 
cloud are known; the current research in this field is not concerned 
with the discovery of new principles but with the treatment of 
cases of increasing complexity. The laws governing the structure 
and behaviour of the nuclei are not so well explored. However, it 
is perfectly certain that some of the most general physical laws are 



214 DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 

valid there too, and with their help far-reaching conclusions can 
be drawn. 

The most important of these laws is that which formulates the 
equivalence of mass (M) and energy (), expressed by the frequently 
quoted formula E = Me 2 where c is the velocity of light. Its general 
derivation was given by EINSTEIN, exactly 50 years ago, with the 
help of relativistic reasoning, long before there existed any possibility 
of an experimental test. The number c is, in ordinary units, centi- 
metres per second, very large, a 3 with 10 zeros behind it; hence 
c* == c x c is extremely large, a 9 with 20. zeros. Therefore the 
change of mass (M = Ejc*} is excessively small for all ordinary 
chemical and physical energy exchanges. In principle a clock 
becomes a little heavier when wound up, but that is absolutely 
immeasurable. The situation is different for nuclear transformations 
where large energies are exchanged. 

A piece of a wall consisting of 100 equal bricks without mortar 
has a weight exactly 100 times that of a single brick; if there is 
mortar the weight is correspondingly higher. The same holds 
roughly for nucleons: a nucleus containing 100 nucleons is about 
100 times as heavy as a single nucleon. Yet only approximately: 
there are deviations, hence there must be a kind of mortar. Now 
strangely enough this mortar appears to have a negative weight: 
the nucleus is lighter than the sum of its constituents. Namely, 
according to EINSTEIN, the mortar is the binding energy which is 
lost when the parts are combined. These 'mass-defects' are con- 
siderable, hence the corresponding energies enormously large. 

The lightest element, hydrogen, consists of one isotope, the single 
proton. (There is also a hydrogen isotope with one additional 
neutron deuteron and one with two neutrons triton.) The 
next element, helium, consists mainly of an isotope having 2 protons 
and 2 neutrons. When these agglomerate energy is liberated, very 
much energy. The process does not occur spontaneously because 
there is an initial obstacle against the combination of the 4 particles, 
some energy has to be spent. The situation is like that of a water 
barrage, the gates of which have to be wound up before the water 
in the reservoir can stream out and do work. The same holds for 
the consecutive elements; they are instable and would combine 
unless there were barrages, fortunately very strong barrages, to 
keep them apart. This is the case in the series of elements up to 
the middle of the whole system, about the place of iron; from there 
on the situation is reversed, each nucleus has the tendency to split 
and is only prohibited to do so by a barrage. The last of the elements 
found in Nature, uranium, has the weakest barrage, and it was this 



DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 215 

one which was first broken in the experiments by HAHN and his 
collaborator STRASSMANN in 1938. 

The way from these delicate laboratory experiments to the first 
uranium reactor (or pile) which was built in Chicago by ENRICO 
FERMI in 19423 was long and demanded an enormous amount of 
ingenuity, courage, skill, organization and money. The decisive 
discovery was that the fission of a uranium nucleus produced by 
the collision with a neutron is accompanied by the emission of 
several neutrons, and that the process could be directed in such a 
way that a sufficient number of these could be prevented from 
escaping or being lost by collisions with impurities as to produce an 
avalanche of new fissions, a self-containing reaction. To begin 
with, nobody could predict the outcome, but Nature has arranged 
it in this manner, hence it was discovered by Man as soon as the 
means were available. That they were available was a historical 
accident, a consequence of the great war. The technological process 
to produce a bomb until its explosion on July i6th, 1945, lasted 
three years and cost about half a billion dollars. 

The inverse process, the fusion of nuclei into higher ones (e.g. 
hydrogen into helium) is the source of energy of the sun and of all 
stars. In the central parts of these the temperatures and pressures 
are so high that the combination of four nucleons is possible in a 
series of steps, through a chain reaction. The same has now been 
accomplished here on earth by using a uranium bomb as ignition. 
Thus we have now the H-bomb, which seemed to be an absolutely 
hellish invention, as no method of abating the violence of the 
explosion was known; but recently it has been announced that 
ways of controlling this reaction have been found. 

There is no doubt any more: all matter is unstable. If this were 
not true the stars would not shine, there would be no heat and light 
from the sun, no life on earth. Stability and life are incompatible. 
Thus life is necessarily a dangerous adventure which may have a 
happy end or a bad one. To-day the problem is how the greatest 
adventure of the human race can be directed towards a happy end. 

Now I wish to say a few words about the blessings which can be 
obtained if men behave reasonably. There is, in the first line, the 
problem of energy. When I was young, half a century ago, the time 
our coal reserves would last was estimated to be a few hundred 
years; petrol oil was not used then on a large scale. Meanwhile an 
enormous amount of coal has been burnt, oil has been discovered 
and used in an ever increasing rate. Yet the estimate of the duration 
of the fossil fuel reserves is still many hundred years. Therefore it 
seems not to be an urgent problem to find new sources of energy. 



2l6 DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 

But this conclusion would be erroneous. Coal and oil are not only 
sources of energy but the most important raw materials for in- 
numerable chemical products. May I just mention the plastics 
and their numerous applications. There will come a time when the 
agricultural output does not suffice for feeding the ever-increasing 
number of human beings. Then chemistry will be challenged to 
produce substitutes, for which, of course, coal is the only available 
raw material. Hence it is barbaric to burn coal and oil. Then the 
social aspect of the question must not be forgotten. The day seems 
to be not far away when in civilized countries no workmen will 
be available who are willing to take up the dark and dangerous 
profession of a miner, at least not for economically bearable wages. 
England seems to approach this state of affairs already. Then there 
are many countries which have neither coal nor oil; for these the 
easily transportable nuclear fuel will be a blessing. 

Another type of the peaceful applications of nuclear physics are 
the radio-active by-products of atomic reactors. Instable, i.e. 
radio-active isotopes of many elements are produced, which can 
be applied to many purposes: as sources of radiation, instead of 
the expensive radium, in medicine, technology, agriculture; for 
instance for the treatment of cancer, the testing of materials, the 
production of new species of plants through mutations. Perhaps 
more important than all this is the idea of 'tracer elements'. By 
adding a small amount of a radio-active isotope to a given element 
it is possible to follow the fate of this element in chemical reactions, 
even in living organisms, by observing the radiation emitted. An 
ever increasing number of experiments in biological chemistry are 
already using this method, which marks a new epoch in our know- 
ledge of the processes of life. 

All this, and what may develop from it in days to come, are 
great things. An international conference at Geneva convened by 
UNO has discussed the exploitation of all these possibilities by a 
collaboration of all nations. I am not a nuclear physicist and have 
not attended it. I hope the labours of this meeting will bring in a 
rich harvest. But I cannot help asking: Can even a technical 
paradise counterbalance the evil of the atomic bomb ? 

I have used the phrase 'paradise on earth' already in the be- 
ginning, but there I meant something different: not technical 
progress, but the realization of the eternal yearning of Man for 
'peace on earth 5 . 

In regard to the opinions I wish to express now, I cannot rely on 
my knowledge of physics, nor on my sporadic studies of history; 
they seem to me just common sense, and they are shared by a 



DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 217 

number of friends, leading scholars from different countries. We 
believe that a major war between Great Powers there exist now 
only two or three has become impossible, or at least will become 
impossible in the near future. For it would lead, as I said already, 
in all likelihood to general destruction, not only of the fighting 
nations but also of the neutrals. GLAUSEWITZ' well known saying 
that \var is the continuation of politics with other means does not 
hold any more, for war has become insanity, and if the human race 
is unable to renounce war its zoological name should not any longer 
be derived from sapientia but from dementia. 

The leading statesmen seem to be well aware of this situation. 
The tuning down of the cold war which we are observing is an 
indication that it is so. The fear of the enormity of the catastrophe 
which might be the result of an armed conflict has led everywhere 
to approaches and negotiations. But fear is a bad foundation for 
reconciliation and solution of conflicts. Is it conceivable that the 
peace resting on fear which we very likely are attaining at present 
may be replaced by something better and more reliable? 

I take it upon me if you regard me as a slightly ridiculous fellow 
who refuses to acknowledge an awkward situation 

Because, he argues trenchantly, 
What must not happen cannot be, 

as the grotesque philosopher PALMSTRdm says in the German poet 
MORGENSTERN'S Songs from the Gallows.* 

However, I am not alone with this view. EINSTEIN shared it and 
has just before his death given a clear statement, together with 
BERTRAND RUSSELL, the great philosopher, and others. A number 
of 1 8 Nobel Laureates, chemists and physicists, gathered for a 
scientific discussion at Lindau, have unanimously accepted a 
declaration (the Mainau Statement) on similar lines. And many 
other people and groups of people have published similar declara- 
tions. May they appear to-day as dreamers: they are the builders 
of the future world. 

But not much time is available for their words to take effect. All 
depends on this, the ability of our generation to re-adjust its thinking 
to the new facts. If it is unable to do so then the days of civilized 
life on earth are coming to an end. And even if all goes well, the 
way will pass very, very close to the abyss. 

* CHRISTIAN MORGENSTERN wrote deep and beautiful poetry which however 
found little resonance in the public. Then he published several little volumes of 
grotesque, apparently senseless verse under the title 'Galgenheder in which he 
caricatured his philosophy through two strange figures, PALMSTROM and KORFF. 
These books had a tremendous and lasting success. 



2l8 DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 

For the world is full of conflicts appearing insoluble: Displaced 
frontiers of countries; expelled populations; antagonism of races, 
languages, national traditions, religions; the bankruptcy of the 
colonial system; and finally the opposing economical ideologies, 
capitalism and communism. Can we really hope that all these 
terrible tensions will be solved without application of force? 

Would it not be preferable, instead of the radical proposition to 
abandon war, to make an attempt to prohibit the new weapons of 
mass destruction by international agreement? This idea seems to 
me (and my friends) impracticable for the following reasons. 

The production of energy through nuclear reactions is already 
being prepared and improved everywhere. A system of supervision 
intended to inhibit the production of weapons of destruction can 
function only in peace time. If war between major powers should 
break out which might initially be conducted with conventional 
weapons the supervision ceases. Is it reasonable to assume that a 
nation in distress but believing that she could save herself with the 
help of the atom bomb would be willing to renounce this last 
resource even if she is liable to suffer badly herself? 

Concerning those 'conventional weapons' I must confess that I 
am unable to understand why they are not causing the same horror, 
the same detestation which is generally felt to-day towards the 
atomic weapons. They have ceased to be honest weapons used by 
soldiers against soldiers and have become means of indiscriminate 
destruction. They are not directed against military objects alone 
but against the whole organization and productive capacity of the 
enemy nation, against factories, railways, houses; they kill the 
helpless, the old, children, women, they destroy the most noble and 
valuable achievements of civilization, churches, schools, monu- 
ments, museums, libraries, without any regard for historical 
importance or irreparability. From the moral standpoint the 
decisive step of warfare towards modern barbarism was the concept 
of total war. Even without atomic weapons the prospect of the 
effects of using ordinary bombs, in combination with chemical and 
bacteriological poisons, is appalling enough. 

Prohibition of atomic weapons alone is not justified, neither 
morally nor by the actual facts. The human race can only be 
saved by renouncing once for all the use of force through war. 
To-day fear has produced such a precarious state of peace. The 
next aim must be to stabilize this peace by strengthening the ethical 
principles which secure the peaceful coexistence of men. CHRIST 
has taught how man ought to behave towards man. The nations 
have up to now acted and the Churches have not objected to this 



DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 21 9 

attitude as if these commandments are valid only inside their 
domains, but not in regard to their mutual relations. That is the 
root of the evil. We can only survive if in the international sphere 
distrust is replaced by understanding, jealousy by the will to help, 
hatred by love. In our time, before our eyes, the doctrine of non- 
violence has been victorious in the hands of a non- Christian, 
MAHATMA GHANDI, who has liberated his country without bloodshed 
(and I do not think that he would have acted differently if his 
adversaries had not been the well-meaning British, but any other 
nation). Why should it not be possible to follow his example? 

I cannot make suggestions for the solution of the actual political 
conflict. Yet I wish to discuss a few general points. 

The first of these is that a tremendous number of men in all 
countries have a personal interest in the preparation, and, if neces- 
sary, the waging of war. There are big industries and many types 
of business who make money from armaments. There are numerous 
men who like the life of a soldier because of its romantic tradition, 
or because they enjoy being rid of responsibility and having just 
to obey. There are the officers: generals, admirals, air marshals, 
etc., whose profession is war. They are still the advisers of present- 
day governments. Finally there are the physicists, chemists, engineers 
who invent new weapons and produce them. It would be an illusion 
to make an attempt of stabilizing the present precarious peace 
without taking any notice of all those people, without giving them 
some substitute for the loss they have to expect. How this can be 
done is beyond my competence except for one class of people, the 
physicists whom I know well. Here I see no great difficulty. 

One hears often hard words about the atomic physicists: all 
calamity is the fault of these brain-athletes, not only the atom bomb 
but also the bad weather. I have endeavoured to show that the 
development of the human mind was bound to lead one day to the 
disclosure and application of the energy stored in the atomic 
nucleus. That this happened so quickly and so thoroughly as to 
lead to a critical situation is the consequence of a tragic historical 
accident: The discovery of the fission of uranium happened just 
at the moment when HITLER acquired power, and just in that 
country, where he acquired power. I, like many others, had then 
to leave Germany and I have seen with my own eyes the panic 
which struck the rest of the world when HITLER'S initial successes 
made it appear possible that he might subjugate all nations of the 
globe. The physicists emigrated from Central Europe knew that 
there was no salvation if the Germans would succeed first to produce 
the atomic bomb. Even EINSTEIN who had been a pacifist all his 



22O DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 

life shared this fear and was persuaded by some young Hungarian 
physicists to warn President ROOSEVELT. Scholars emigrated from 
Europe contributed much to the uranium project, the most prom- 
inent of them ENRICO FERMI, perhaps the greatest experimental 
physicist of our time next to RUTHERFORD. The direction of the 
scheme remained in American hands. It seems to me that no blame 
can be attached to the men who constructed the atom bomb unless 
one accepts the teaching of extreme pacifism that power should 
never be used even against the greatest evil. It is quite a different 
matter with the application of the bombs against Japan in the last 
phase of the war. I personally consider this to be a barbaric act, 
and a foolish one. Responsible for it are not only politicians and 
soldiers, but a small group of scientists who advised the deciding 
committee appointed by President TRUMAN. One of these, FERMI, 
has died meanwhile. Another, from reasons of conscience, has 
given up all scientific activity, has become the head of a great 
educational institution and works against the misuse of science. 
Other members of this group have, as far as I know, not essentially 
changed their life and activities, nor presumably their opinion about 
the necessity of dropping the bombs on Japanese cities. If you wish 
to get a glimpse of the psychology of the atomic physicists read 
the clever and amusing book by LAURA FERMI, the widow of the 
physicist, Atoms in the Family. The title of its last chapter is e A New 
Toy, the Giant Cyclotron 3 . This word toy is significant, though 
perhaps overdrawn. These men are swallowed up by their problems 
and are triumphant if a solution is found, but ponder little about 
the consequences of the results. And if they do so then with the 
feeling: this is beyond our sphere of influence. The idea to abandon 
research because its effects might be dangerous seems absurd to 
them; for if they give up there would be plenty of others to con- 
tinue, and in particular if the Americans were not on top, the Rus- 
sians would be. And all, apart from a limited number, have after 
the war returned to peaceful occupations, to research and teaching, 
and they desire nothing better. Societies have been formed amongst 
them to discuss and study the social responsibility of scientists and 
to oppose the misuse of the discoveries. 

There are of course a few physicists who have tasted power and 
liked it, who are ambitious and want to preserve the influential 
positions acquired during the war. But altogether I think that the 
ideal of politics without force will be less resisted by scientists than 
by other social groups. Even the ambitious and worldly scientists 
will be satisfied by directing big projects of development and advising 
the administrations of states in general politics. The consequences 



DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 221 

of the appearance of this type of men for the development of 
science itself are outside the frame of this discussion. May I be 
allowed to express my personal opinion that from the standpoint 
of fundamental research this development may turn out deplorable, 
perhaps disastrous. The appearance of a new EINSTEIN is hardly 
to be expected in such environments. 

On the other hand, an admixture of scientists in politics and 
administration seems to me an advantage because they are less 
dogmatic and more open to argument than people trained in law 
or classics. To illustrate this let me record a recent personal 
experience. 

There was the usual yearly gathering of Nobel Laureates, chemists 
and a few physicists, at Lindau, Lake Konstanz, in July, for dis- 
cussing scientific problems. OTTO HAHN, WERNER HEISENBERG and 
myself submitted to them a declaration (called the Mainau State- 
ment) prepared by us in collaboration with some other scholars of 
different countries, in which the danger of the present situation 
was emphasized and the abandonment of war demanded. Most of 
the participants agreed at once, but a few had doubts. A famous 
American scholar objected: I have just come from a visit to Israel 
and convinced myself that the existence of this little nation can be 
secured against the pressure of the Arabs only by the force of arms'. 
That is plausible enough. But in the end he accepted our arguments 
(the same as given here) and he signed the declaration with the 
rest of us. 

Exactly the same objection is made wherever the last wars have 
left painful wounds, where boundaries have been shifted, popula- 
tions expelled as in Israel, Korea, Indo-China, Germany. 

I myself have experienced enough to know what it means to be 
the victim of political persecution. I was allowed to return to my 
home country Germany, but my proper home land Silesia, which 
is now a part of Poland, is closed to me. That is a painful loss. But 
fate has decided. To redress the situation by force is impossible 
without much worse injustice and, very likely, general destruction. 
We have to learn resignation, we have to practice understanding, 
tolerance, the will to help instead of threats and force. Otherwise 
the end of civilized man is near. 

For I believe that BERTRAND RUSSELL is right if he never tires of 
repeating: Our choice is only between Co-existence and Non- 
existence. Let me end by quoting his words: 

Tor countless ages the sun rose and set, the moon waxed and waned, 
the stars shone in the night, but it was only with the coming of Man 
that these things were understood. In the great world of astronomy 



222 DEVELOPMENT AND ESSENCE OF THE ATOMIC AGE 

and in the little world of the atom, Man has unveiled secrets which 
might have been thought undiscoverable. In art and literature and 
religion, some men have shown a sublimity of feeling, which makes 
the species worth preserving. Is all this to end in trivial horror because 
so few are able to think of Man rather than of this or that group of 
men ? Is one race so destitute of wisdom, so incapable of impartial 
love, so blind even to the simplest dictates of self-preservation, that 
the last proof of its silly cleverness is to be the extermination of all 
life on our planet? for it will be not only men who will perish, but 
also the animals and plants, whom no one can accuse of communism 
or anti-communism I cannot believe that this is to be the end.' 

If we all refuse to believe this, and act accordingly, it will not be 
the end. 



A NEW YEAR'S MESSAGE 

(From Physikalische Bldtter, vol. u, Jan. i, 1955.) 

MUCH has changed in physics during the two decades I spent 
abroad. It is no longer the quiet, pure science of old, but a 
decisive factor in the power politics of nations. I have only been a 
bystander of the revolution brought about by HAHN'S discovery of 
uranium fission. It seems to me that the physicists of Germany 
are not as conscious of this completely changed situation as those 
of the Anglo-Saxon countries. There nobody can avoid the question 
of conscience how far he wants to collaborate in the development 
of forces which threaten the very existence of the civilized world. 
I have often asked myself how Lord RUTHERFORD, the actual 
founder of nuclear physics, would behave. He certainly was a 
patriot and helped in the defence of his country during the First 
World War. But he drew limits. When I came to Cambridge in 
1933 FRITZ HABER was also there, ill and spiritually broken through 
exile from his fatherland. I tried to bring him together with 
RUTHERFORD; but he refused to shake hands with the originator 
of chemical warfare. How would RUTHERFORD behave today? 
He might have been able through the weight of his personality to 
stop the unconditional surrender of means of destruction to politi- 
cians and military. Some leading physicists of America have tried 
just that, but without success. There is the document in which they 
warned the American government not to use the atom bomb against 
highly populated towns and in whi.ch they predicted correctly the 
political and moral consequences it is known under the name of 
the Franck Report after the chairman, my old friend JAMES FRANCK. 
In America and England societies have been formed which aim 
at solving the question of the social responsibility of the scientist. 
As example I mention the American 'Society for Social Responsi- 
bility in Science' (S.S.R.S.), of which I am a member. This 
association informs its members by monthly news letters,* in these 
we are told about discussions, talks, publications and books, and 
given extracts from them, also statements are published by well 
known men and women and finally letters from the readers are 
printed. In the last number there are extracts from a letter by 
ALBERT SCHWEITZER to the London Daily Herald about the hydrogen 
bomb and also sentences from a lecture (Alex Wood Memorial 



223 



224 A NEW DEAR'S MESSAGE 

Lecture 1954) by Professor KATHLEEN LONSDALE, the well-known 
crystallographer, who became one of the first female members of 
the Royal Society. She is a Quaker and a protagonist against the 
misuse of scientific inventions for inhuman and political ends; she 
is just back from a world trip via India and Japan to Australia 
where she spread her ideas. She is a leader in English societies 
which have similar aims. 

As far as I know there is no such organization yet in Germany, 
and that is only natural in view of the limitations which have been 
placed on the German scientists by the occupation statute. But the 
time has come when a new obligation arises from the lifting of this 
restraint and with it the need for clarification of these problems. 
It seems to me that the German Physical Society could be a forum 
for such discussions. It is not by any means only a matter of the 
most fundamental questions such as attitude towards war in 
general and towards the use of means of destruction, which threaten 
the existence of whole nations or even of all of civilized mankind. 
But it is also a matter of the lesser and nevertheless important prob- ' 
lems which are concerned with the relation of the scientist to society. 
To select a few points: 

The threatening of freedom of science by military supervision 
of research and censorship of publication, the spy witch-hunt as 
it is now rampant in the United States, the founding of numerous 
well-equipped state laboratories through which an increasing 
number of scientists fall into dependence; finally the grave question 
whether the successful researcher shall always remain only an 
expert assistant or take a responsible part in important decisions. 

German physics has achieved an enormous rebuilding of her 
research and teaching materials in the few years since the collapse. 
Let her use with equal verve the perhaps only short time between 
now and complete freedom of action to clarify moral and social 
questions which have been forced on the physicist in his role as 
human being and citizen as a result of his own researches. If this 
is left undone the freedom of science will be as greatly threatened 
as the civic freedom of the individual scientist. And this problem 
of responsibility is as international as science herself, A uniting of 
the groups which discuss this in the different countries would 
therefore be highly desirable. 



FROM THE POSTSCRIPT TO "THE 
RESTLESS UNIVERSE " (1951) 

CONCLUSION 

WE have reached the end of our journey into the depth of matter. 
We have sought for firm ground and found none. The deeper 
we penetrate, the more restless becomes the universe, and the 
vaguer and cloudier. It is said that ARCHIMEDES, full of pride in 
his machines, cried, e Give me a place to stand, and I will move 
the world!' There is no fixed place in the Universe: all is rushing 
about and vibrating in a wild dance. But not for that reason only 
is ARCHIMEDES' saying pontifical. To move the world would mean 
contravening its laws; but these are strict and invariable. 

The scientist's urge to investigate, like the faith of the devout or 
the inspiration of the artist, is an expression of mankind's longing 
for something fixed, something at rest in the universal whirl: God, 
Beauty, Truth. 

Truth is what the scientist aims at. He finds nothing at rest, 
nothing enduring, in the universe. Not everything is knowable, 
still less predictable. But the mind of man is capable of grasping 
and understanding at least a part of Creation; amid the flight of 
phenomena stands the immutable pole of law. 

So schafF ich am sausenden Webstuhl der Zeit 
Und wirke der Gottheit lebendiges Kleid. 

GOETHE, Faust. 

'Tis thus at the roaring Loom of Time I ply, 

And weave for God the Garment thou seest Him by. 

(CARLYLE'S translation.) 

POSTSCRIPT 

Since I wrote the last lines, 15 years ago, great and formidable 
events have happened. The dance of atoms, electrons and nuclei, 
which in all its fury is subject to God's eternal laws, has been 
entangled with another restless Universe which may well be the 
Devil's: the human struggle for power and domination, which 
eventually becomes history. My optimistic enthusiasm about the 
disinterested search for truth has been severely shaken. I wonder 
at my simplemindedness when I re-read what I said on the modern 
fulfilment of the alchemists 5 dream: 

225 



226 FROM THE POSTSCRIPT TO "THE RESTLESS UNIVERSE" (1951) 

'Now however, the motive is not the lust for gold, cloaked by the 
mystery of magic arts, but the scientists' pure curiosity. For it is 
clear from the beginning that we may not expect wealth too.' 

Gold means power, power to rule and to have a big share in the 
riches of this world. Modern alchemy is even a short-cut to this 
end, it provides power directly; a power to dominate and to 
threaten and hurt on a scale never heard of before. And this power 
we have actually seen displayed in ruthless acts of warfare, in the 
devastation of whole cities and the destruction of their population. 
Such acts, of course, have been achieved by other means. In the 
same war other cities than Hiroshima, with a considerable percentage 
of their population, have been destroyed a little slower by ordinary 
explosives. Every previous war had its technical 'progress' in 
destruction, back to the stone age when the first bronze weapons 
conquered flint axes and arrow heads. Still there is a difference. 
Many states, populations, civilizations have perished through 
superior power, but there were vast regions unaffected and room 
was left for new growth. To-day the globe has become small, and the 
human race is confronted with the possibility of final self-destruction. 

When the question of a new edition of this book arose I felt a 
considerable embarrassment. To bring it up-to-date I had to 
write an account of the scientific development since 1935. But 
although this period is as full of fascinating discoveries, ideas, 
theories, as any previous epoch, I could not possibly describe them 
in the same tone in which the book was written; namely, in the 
belief that a deep insight into the workshop of nature was the first 
step towards a rational philosophy and to worldly wisdom. It seems 
to me that the scientists who led the way to the atomic bomb were 
extremely skilful and ingenious, but not wise men. They delivered 
the fruits of their discoveries unconditionally into the hands of 
politicians and soldiers; thus they lost their moral innocence and 
their intellectual freedom. 

-On July 1 6, 1945, the first experimental bomb exploded near 
Los Alamos, New Mexico. This was certainly one of the greatest 
triumphs of theoretical physics if measured not by the subtlety of 
ideas but by the effort made in money, scientific collaboration and 
industrial organization. No preliminary experiment was possible, 
the tremendous risk was taken in the confidence that the theoretical 
calculations based on laboratory experiments were accurate. There- 
fore it is no wonder that the physicists who watched the terrific 
phenomenon of the first nuclear explosion felt proud and relieved 
from a heavy responsibility. They had done a great service to their 
country and to the community of allied nations. 



FROM THE POSTSCRIPT TO "THE RESTLESS UNIVERSE" (1951) 227 

But when, a few weeks later, two 'atomic bombs 5 were dropped 
over Japan and destroyed the crowded cities of Hiroshima and 
Nagasaki, they discovered that a more fundamental responsibility 
was on their shoulders. 

The world had become pretty callous against the horrors of the 
war. HITLER'S seed had grown. His was the idea of total war, and 
his bombs smashed Rotterdam and Coventry. But he found keen 
pupils. In the end the bombers of both sides succeeded in a sys- 
tematic devastation of Central Europe. A great part of its historic 
and artistic treasures, the inheritance of thousands of years went up 
in flames. An architectural jewel like Dresden was destroyed in 
one of the last days of the European war, and 100,000 civilians, men,, 
women and children, are said to have perished with it. I do not 
doubt that those responsible for this act can rightfully claim tactical 
and strategical necessity; and the world in general found sufficient 
justifications, ranging from blind hatred and the wish of retribution 
to the quasi-humane idea that to shorten the war all means are 
good enough. Ethical standards had fallen sharply, indeed. 

Still the two atomic bombs dropped on Japan made a stir, and 
when details of the human tragedy became known there was 
something like an awakening of conscience in many parts of the 
world. 

.This is not the place to express my personal judgment of the 
statesmen who decided to use this brutal application of power. 
Cases of precedence are plentiful there is not much difference in 
the responsibility for killing 20,000 in one night or 50,000 in one 
minute. But being a scientist I am concerned with the question of 
how far science and scientists share the responsibility. 

The motives of those who took part in the development of nuclear 
explosives were certainly above reproach : Many of them were just 
drafted to this work as their war service, others joined it, driven by 
the apprehension that the Germans might produce the bomb first. 
Yet there was no organization of scientists which could form a 
general opinion. Single men became little cog-wheels in the 
tremendous machine, which was directed by political and military 
authorities. The leading physicists became scientific advisers of 
these authorities and experienced the new sensation of power and 
influence. They enjoyed their work and its tremendous success^ 
and forgot for the time being to think hard about its consequences. 
It is true that a group of scientists warned the U.S. Government 
not to use the bomb against cities, but to demonstrate its existence 
and power in a less murderous way, for instance on the top of 
Fujiyama mountain. They predicted very accurately the disastrous 



228 FROM THE POSTSCRIPT TO "THE RESTLESS UNIVERSE 9 ' (1951) 

political consequences which an attack on a city would have. But 
their advice was neglected. 

The principal discrepancy between public opinion in the United 
States and the conviction of the scientists is concerned with secrecy. 
The scientists are convinced that there is no secret in science. 
There may be technical tricks which can be kept secret for a limited 
period. But the laws of nature are open to anybody who is trained 
in using the scientific method of research. 

Therefore it was futile to keep the atomic bomb project from 
being known to the Russian allies, and the maintenance of this 
secret has with necessity transformed them from old friends into 
enemies. They felt menaced by a tremendous new weapon; they 
started to develop it themselves, and they obtained it in a shorter 
time than was ever expected. 

On the other hand this phantom of secrecy had disastrous effects 
on the development of nuclear physics in America. Many physicists 
have been subjected to suspicion and even to accusation of dis- 
loyalty. The whole of science has been hampered by the classifica- 
tion of discoveries into secret and open ones, and by the supervision 
of publication. There is no doubt that certain security measures, 
mainly in regard to technical questions, are unavoidable. But the 
subordination of fundamental research to political and military 
authorities is detrimental. The scientists themselves have learned 
"by now that the period of unrestricted individualism in research 
has come to an end. They know that even the most abstract and 
remote ideas may one day become of great practical importance 
like EINSTEIN'S law of equivalence of mass and energy. They have 
begun to organize themselves and to discuss the problem of their 
responsibility to human society. It would be left to these organiza- 
tions to find a way to harmonise the security of the nations with the 
freedom of research and publication without which science must 
stagnate. 

The release of nuclear energy is an event comparable to the first 
fire kindled by prehistoric man though there is no modern 
Prometheus but teams of clever yet less heroic fellows, useless as 
inspiration for epic poetry. Many believe that the new discoveries 
may lead either to immense progress or to equal catastrophe, io 
paradise or to hell. I, however, think that this earth will remain 
what it always was; a mixture of heaven and hell, a battlefield of 
angels and devils. Let us have a look around: what are the 
prospects of this battle, and what can we do to help the good cause? 

To begin with the devil's part, there i$ the hydrogen bomb. We 
have seen that, though almost all matter is unstable in principle. 



FROM THE POSTSCRIPT TO "THE RESTLESS UNIVERSE" (1951) 22 

we are protected against nuclear catastrophe by the low temperatures 
on earth, which even in our hottest furnaces are quite insufficient 
to initiate nuclear fusion. But the discovery of fission has destroyed 
this security. The temperature in an exploding uranium bomb is 
presumably high enough to start the fusion of hydrogen with the 
help of the e carbon cycle 5 , which is the source of stellar energy, or a 
similar catalytic process. Thus an explosive of many thousand times 
higher efficiency than the fission bomb could be made from a 
material available in abundance. Of course, work has started with 
the usual argumentation: if we do not do it, the other fellow (mean- 
ing the Russian) will. If it succeeds there will be a new instrument 
of wholesale destruction, but no peaceful application of the new 
forces seems to be possible. No way is known to slow down fusion 
in order to use it as a fuel. A perfectly hellish prospect. 

Fission however has many and far-reaching applications of a 
peaceful kind. It can be used as fuel, since the reaction velocity can 
be controlled. Each pile produces an enormous amount of heat 
which at present is wasted in most cases. Power stations using 
uranium or thorium as fuel are possible, as the difficulties connected 
with the pernicious radiation could certainly be overcome. The 
question is however an economic one. The raw material is rare, 
and if the same amount of energy which is at present made from 
coal would be produced by nuclear reactors, the whole uranium 
ore at present or in future available would be used up in less than 
half a century. Hence it is improbable that the new fuel will be 
able to compete with coal and oil. Under certain conditions, how- 
ever, this may be the case, namely where the advantage of the small 
bulk and weight of nuclear fuel, as compared with that of coal or 
oil, is decisive. There is a possibility of increasing the efficiency of 
fission by 'breeding', i.e. by directing the process in a pile in such 
a way that a great proportion of the nuclei present is transformed 
into fissionable isotopes. This would mean an extension of the raw 
material over a much longer period. 

Apart from the still problematic application of nuclear reactions 
for power production, there are numerous others which have already 
led to great progress'and which are more promising. There is first 
the generation of new isotopes in the pile. Our knowledge of the 
stability of nuclei and of the laws of their interaction has been 
immensely increased. Some of the radio-active products can be 
used in medicine for therapeutical purposes, replacing for instance 
radium in the fight against cancer. The most important application 
is the so-called 'tracer method' which is revolutionizing chemistry 
and biology. Already in the first period of radio-activity v. HEVESY 



230 FROM THE POSTSCRIPT TO "THE RESTLESS UNIVERSE" (I95 1 ) 

had the idea to trace the fate of atoms in chemical or biological 
processes by adding to them a small amount of a radio-active 
isotope. This discloses its presence by radiation, and as the methods 
of detection of radiation are extremely sensitive, one can thus deter- 
mine much smaller amounts of an element than with the balance. 
It is even possible to investigate the distribution of atoms in living 
tissue. The actual application of this idea was formerly restricted 
to the few atomic types for which naturally radio-active isotopes 
were known. Isotopes are now available for almost all elements of 
the periodic system. The work on this line, though hardly begun, 
has already led to important results, and will lead to still more. 

But what are these important results compared with the spectre 
lurking in the background, the possibility of atomic warfare on a 
great scale? 

In combination with other infernal contraptions, like rockets to 
deliver bombs at large distances, chemical, biological and radio- 
active poisons, such a war must mean a degree of human suffering 
and degradation which is beyond the power of imagination. No 
country would be immune, but those with highly developed industry 
would suffer most. It is very doubtful whether our technological 
civilization would survive such a catastrophe. One may be inclined 
to regard this as no great loss, but as a just punishment for its 
shortcomings and sins: the lack of productive genius in art and 
literature, the neglect of the moral teachings of religion and 
philosophy, the slowness to abandon outdated political conceptions, 
like national sovereignty. Yet we are all involved in this tragedy, 
and the instinct of self-preservation, the love of our children, makes 
us think about a way of salvation. 

There are the two political colossi, U.S.A. and U.S.S.R., both 
pretending to aim at nothing but peace, but both rearming with all 
their power to defend their ideology and way of life, and between 
them is a weak and divided Europe, trying to steer a middle course. 
Both sides are greedily devouring the latest achievements of 
scientific technology for their armed forces. Both have some kind 
of theory for .their way of life in which they believe with an amazing 
fanaticism. Yet the foundations of these theories are rather doubtful. 
They use the same words for different or even opposite ideas, as for 
instance 'democracy*, which in the West means a system of parlia- 
mentary representation freely and secretly elected, but in the East 
means something quite different and hard to formulate (a compli- 
cated economic and political pyramid of bureaucracy which aims 
at representing, and working for, e the people') . In other ways the 
American theory is much vaguer than the Russian, and that seems 



FROM THE POSTSCRIPT TO "THE RESTLESS UNIVERSE " (1951) 231 

to have a historical reason. America has grown by expansion in a 
practical vacuum; the pioneers of the West had to overcome terrific 
natural obstacles, but negligible human resistance. The Russia of 
today had to conquer not only natural but human difficulties: she 
had to break up the rotten system of the Czars and to assimilate 
backward Asiatic tribes; now she has set herself the task of bringing 
her brand of modernization to the ancient civilizations of the Far 
East. For this purpose it is indispensable to have a well-defined 
doctrine full of slogans, which appeals to the needs and instincts 
of the poverty-stricken masses. Thus one understands the power 
which MAJRX'S philosophy has gained in the East. What can we 
scientists do in this conflict? We can join the spiritual, religious, 
philosophical forces, which reject war on ethical grounds. We can 
even attack the ideological foundations of the conflict itself. For 
science is not only the basis of technology but also the material 
for a sound philosophy. And the development of modern physics 
has enriched our thinking by a new principle of fundamental 
importance, the idea of complementarity. The fact that in an 
exact science like physics there are found mutually exclusive and 
complementary situations which cannot be described by the same 
concepts but need two kinds of expressions, can be applied to other 
fields of human activity and thought. Some such applications to 
biology and psychology were suggested by NIELS BOHR. In philo- 
sophy there is the ancient and central problem of free will. Any 
act of willing can be regarded on the one side as a spontaneous 
process in the conscious mind, on the other as a product of motives 
depending on past or present impressions from the outside world. 
If one assumes that the latter are subject to deterministic laws of 
nature, one has a conflict between the feeling of freedom of action 
and the necessity of a natural process. But if one regards this as 
an example of complementarity the apparent contradiction turns 
out to be nothing but an epistemological error. This is a healthy 
way of thinking, which properly applied may remove many violent 
disputes not only in philosophy but in all ways of life: for instance 
in politics. 

Marxian philosophy, which is a hundred years old, knows of 
course nothing of this new principle. However, a prominent 
Russian scientist has recently attempted to interpret it from the 
standpoint of 'dialectic materialism', which teaches that all thinking 
consists of a thesis opposed by an antithesis; after some struggle, 
they are combined in a synthesis. In this Marxian dogma, so he 
claims, you have the prediction of what has happened in physics, 
for instance in optics: NEWTON'S thesis that light consists of particles 



232 FROM THE POSTSCRIPT TO "THE RESTLESS UNIVERSE*' (1951) 

was opposed by HUYGENS' antithesis that it consists of waves, until 
both were united in the synthesis of quantum mechanics. That is 
all very well and indisputable, though a little trivial. But why not 
go further and apply it to the two competing ideologies: Liberalism 
(or Capitalism) and Communism, as thesis and anti- thesis ? Then 
one would expect a synthesis of some kind, instead of the Marxian 
doctrine of the complete and permanent victory of communism. 
It can hardly be expected that the ideas of MARX, developed about 
100 years ago, can throw much light on the development of modern 
science. The opposite is more likely: that the new philosophical 
ideas developed by science during these 100 years may help towards 
a deeper understanding of social and political relations. Indeed, 
we find two systems of thought which deal with the same structure, 
the state, in completely different, apparently contradictory ways. 
One starts from the freedom of the individual as the basic concep- 
tion, the other from the collective interest of the community. 

This distinction corresponds roughly to the two aspects of the 
problem of willing which we have just mentioned: the subjective 
feeling of freedom on the one hand, the causal chain of motives on 
the other. Thus the West idealises political and economical 
liberalism, the East collective life regulated by an all-powerful 
state. But as it seems likely that the contradiction in the problem 
of free will can be solved by applying the idea of complementarity, 
the same will hold for the contradiction of political ideologies. 
Thus the intellectual gulf between West and East may be bridged, 
and that is the service which natural philosophy can offer in the 
present crisis. 

The world which is so ready to use the gifts of science for mass 
destruction would do well to listen to this message of reconciliation 
and co-operation.